Texts:Rom-E-17a-DHS-A

Revision as of 13:38, 3 November 2024 by Robbie (talk | contribs) (1 revision imported)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

¶1

I don’t suggest the emperor had no clothes.[1] We all admire John Dewey’s work; it formed and inspired us. He thought extensively, worked hard, and composed an unparalleled corpus, exemplary in scope and influence. Yet his thought looms large, especially among theorists of education. Do we overvalue it, narrowing our horizon to his concerns?

¶2

Dewey lived a human life, like ourselves, like the woman in the next office, the man down the hall, or those in the pantheon—Plato, Aquinas, Descartes, or Nietzsche. All of us, the raw student and the hallowed name, are simply human. As we meet—in and across both time and space—we do so as peers, toe to toe, at once equals yet each unique.

¶3

And in our interactions, comprising human, all-too-human lives, we try to judge ourselves and others rightly even though the just estimation never gets given, clearly marked as true. Judging worth in the face of uncertainty, we approximate sound evaluation, an estimate that fluctuates around positives and negatives, we modulate our estimates, never able to claim certainty, fully attained.

¶4

Further complicating the positives and negatives, a double uncertainty arises from the interactive flux of life. What strengths and weaknesses do we perceive in those whom we assess? And how do our affinities and aversions, our own dispositions—enthused, credulous, worldly, cautious, skeptical—bias our perceptions of others?

¶5

We all learn that we might err in perceiving. In Hans Christian Andersen’s beloved tale, the swindling weavers played on this caution to get the emperor and his people, the high and the low, to misjudge what plainly met their eyes. While weaving the emperor’s finery, the pair repeatedly warned everyone that their handiwork would appear invisible to the “unusually stupid” or someone “unfit for his office.” Together, this combination can induce big errors in the shared estimate of reputations.

¶6

On one side, mystified by something of high repute, but feeling devoid of pretension about it, we are all inclined to hold ourselves unusually stupid—of course, not globally, but with the specific at hand. “I just don’t get it. But who am I? If they say it’s so, it must be right”—be it classical music, abstract art, macroeconomics, or whatever. But by itself, the ordinary person’s self-effacement wouldn’t have made the weavers’ swindle work, for prudent expertise would dependably have spoken up. But it didn’t. Those, like us, who fancy we enjoy some repute, relative to a matter in repute, avoid seeming unfit for our status, seriously biasing our judgment. If I can’t see a virtue that other experts see, or if another discovers a virtue that I fail to perceive, I lose face and maybe even more.

¶7

Hence, as a public reputation grows, good or bad, ordinary complaisance and expert conformity both strengthen. With this combination at work, a misperception builds and persists, as in Andersen’s tale. The swindle worked until a child blurted out, “he hasn’t got anything on!” Being too naive to doubt what she saw, and too young to have her motive questioned, she made the misjudgment obvious to all and even the shivering emperor suspected she was right.

¶8

Having reached an age and status often described as a second childhood, I will say what seems plain to me. Through a combination of general complaisance and expert conformism, we educational theorists have inflated Dewey’s deserved reputation far beyond what the quality of his work can sustain. Less naïve than Andersen’s child, I state my view as a reasoned hypothesis, indicating why I think it merits consideration.

¶9

First, in “Reconstructing Reconstruction,” I recount briefly how Dewey initially formed an aspiration to act, putting forth a program for reconstruction in philosophy, education, and social life. Through reconstruction he sought to overcome chronic dislocations in social life by rejecting the faulty intellectual heritage that had induced and sustained them, replacing it with generative ideas, soundly grounded instrumentalities for a more humane conduct of life. Second, in “Reconstruction, Just So,” I indicate the nub of my hypothesis, namely that Dewey pursued the negative part of his program for reconstruction—his rejection of past thinkers and their thinking—through a vacuous form of historical reason, weakening his positive program for a naturalistic humanism, one more instrumental in the art of living. Here I explain my hypothesis by sampling a spectrum of evidence selectively. Then in the 3rd and 4th sections, “Dewey’s Persistent Kantian Misconstruction” and “Woozling in Reverse,” I criticize Dewey on Kant and Hegel, showing how a misplaced animus weakened how he mobilized historical resources for his work. In the 5th section, “Envoi,” I suggest how historical reason can anticipate future possibilities and thus inform present action, and I call on all to use it in humanizing the life world we share.

Reconstructing Reconstruction

¶10

Scholars have documented Dewey’s life and work thoroughly.[2] My thesis does not rest on newly discovered materials. Let’s ground it instead by looking at available materials in a more critical spirit than has been the norm. But first, we need to note some highpoints in Dewey’s education and early career as he formed an active program for reconstruction in philosophy, education, and society, which he then steadily pursued through his mature work.

¶11

Thinking precedes thought; acting before action. Youthful wondering preceded Dewey’s formed ideas about reconstruction. Looking back at 71, Dewey narrated how active goals of reconstruction engaged him long before he linked them with that term. As an undergraduate, religious conflicts roiled him and “social interests and problems” moved him. Exploring those in the college library, Dewey encountered Harriet Martineau’s presentation of Auguste Comte’s positive philosophy. Much in it did not catch his interest, “but [Comte’s] idea of the disorganized character of Western modern culture, due to a disintegrative ‘individualism,’ and his idea of a synthesis of science that should be a regulative method of an organized social life, impressed me deeply.” (LW5: 153-4)[3] Here Dewey succinctly identified the start of his lifelong commitment to reconstruction, an effort to cut the disintegrative individualism endemic in Western culture from its roots, replacing it with an instrumental synthesis of science regulating the organization of social life.[4]

¶12

Graduating in 1879, still a raw youth of only 20 years, Dewey took 15 years to form his Comtean aspiration fully into his program for reconstruction in philosophy, education, and society. He marked time for three years, earned his Ph.D. in two, and then started teaching at the University of Michigan at 25 in 1884. In 1886, he married Alice Chipman, and soon he had a growing family, a straitened budget, and a full calendar of activity. Success was less an achievement, more an imperative. A research scholar, he produced: articles in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Andover Review, Science, Bibliotheca Sacra, and a bunch in the prestigious journal, Mind. In 1887, his substantial textbook, Psychology, won good reviews and wide course adoptions. A year later, his careful critique, Leibniz's New Essays Concerning the Human Understanding, followed. At 28, his career was off and running and would continue unabated for another 65 years.

¶13

Catapulting as a student and novice professor through the 1880s, Dewey rapidly absorbed knowledge and a professional role, that of an emerging authority in the history of philosophy with an interest in philosophical psychology, the rising protégé of Professor George Morris. Dewey’s first two books and his essays prior to 1889 fit this role, advancing views quite different from the program for reconstruction in philosophy that he would soon start enunciating.[5] Late in the decade, however, Dewey began to break from Morris. In 1888, Dewey jumped to the University of Minnesota, in search of better pay and a clearer path up the academic ranks. Early in 1889, an event erased any potential ambivalence about going it alone. Morris died unexpectedly. That fall, at 30, Dewey returned, newly promoted, to head Michigan’s philosophy department. Dewey grasped his main chance, blossoming as he defined his distinctive life work.

¶14

Reconstruction had already entered Dewey’s vocabulary in two distinct senses. The first came from the faculty psychology of Dewey’s youth, indicating what the imagination does in reconstructing stored-away data into active memories.[6] Dewey spoke of reconstruction in this established sense in his first book, Psychology: “Our past experiences are gone.... They have no existence until the mind reconstructs them.” (EW2: 155) Examples of this usage scatter throughout Dewey’s work, generalized to apply to various mental activities, for instance, most famously in Dewey’s definitions of education: “We thus reach a technical definition of education: It is that reconstruction or reorganization of experience which adds to the meaning of experience, and which increases ability to direct the course of subsequent experience.” (MW9: 82) As here, this usage frequently appeared reinforced with synonyms, and Dewey used this ordinary sense, sometimes strategically, again as here, but not distinctively, in common with all who speak of the process of reconstructing one thing or another.

¶15

In his book on Leibniz, Dewey had introduced a second sense of reconstruction, indicating not what minds generally do, but what philosophers specifically do. He extracted the root meaning from Descartes: “the method of philosophy consists in the analysis of any complex group of ideas down to simple ideas which shall be perfectly clear and distinct; that all such clear and distinct ideas are true, and may then be used for the synthetic reconstruction of any body of truth.” (EW2: 272) Later in the work, Dewey began to give it a more systemic sense: if altering a key idea transformed controlling, foundational concepts, working the reconstruction fully through would fully transform a system of thought. Dewey described how Leibniz, pace Locke, found no grounds for necessity in experience. Hence, “both form and content, accordingly, need to be reconstructed [by Leibniz] if they are to be worthy of the name of science or of knowledge.” (EW2: 326, cf. 416) More than a method for doing philosophy, Dewey made it the basis for a life agenda of work.

¶16

Reconstructing, in its first sense, as a mental activity, occurs throughout Dewey’s work. We may encounter it, but not as a primary concern. Reconstruction, in its second sense, as a philosophic transformation carried through by specific thinkers, also occurs throughout Dewey’s work. In this sense, reconstruction indicated the outcome of philosophic inquiry and argumentation more than the unfolding of a general intellectual process. This reconstruction made past sources of error and discord inoperative and replaced them with instrumental resources for guiding current and future activity. We will concentrate on it in criticizing the program Dewey developed and pursued as his life work, reconstruction in philosophy, education, and social life.

¶17

Following Morris’s death, Dewey rapidly developed his program of reconstruction. By 1890-91, in essays on the self in relation to Kant and Hegel (EW3: 56-74), on moral theory and practice (EW3: 93-109), and on logical theory (EW3: 125-141), Dewey repeatedly used the concept of reconstruction in explaining the fundamental contradiction in contemporary life between the promise of scientific rationality and the senescence of accompanying metaphysical ideas about human action and morality. He structured the last essay on the present position of logical theory to explain the task the reconstructive agenda would take up. “Science has got far enough along to make its negative attitude towards previous codes of life evident, while its own positive principle of reconstruction is not yet evident.” These reflections climaxed in questioning where logical theory stood in the present: “when we speak of the rationality, of the intrinsic meaning of fact, can these terms be understood in their direct and obvious sense, and not in any remote, or merely metaphysical sense?” (EW3: 125-129) This and similar questions rhetorically implied a reconstruction in logic and thought, one that required our “acting on it, only ambulando,” on our feet: to allow scientific rationality to guide practical life by putting a stop to remote, metaphysical thought (EW3:140-141).

¶18

Two years later, James Tufts recommended his friend and colleague Dewey to head the philosophy department at the University of Chicago. Up to this time, Dewey had integrated his philosophic career into a context of Christian observance, conventional through the 19th century in American higher education. A small community, Ann Arbor clustered some 10,000 people around an academic institution that fulfilled familiar collegiate roles with intimations of becoming a large research and teaching institution. Already, Dewey had been taking the train west from Ann Arbor to Chicago, 5 hours or so, to participate in the social reform activities of Hull House. And Chicago’s philosophy department included pedagogy, a path to apply reconstruction directly in life. With the move, he could better put his reconstructive program into practice.

¶19

Mid-May 1894, Michigan students, sad and proud, hung Dewey’s portrait in Newberry Hall, and gathered to hear him address the Students’ Christian Association one last time. “No one can afford to miss the privilege of hearing him.” (CJD1: #00125)[7] Dewey was not merely moving from one university to another; he was marking a significant change in his work and the context he set it in. He bid farewell to an academic institution and to its students, but the institution and his students were an ethos of activity, a community, a way of living with which he had identified. Dewey simply called his farewell, “Reconstruction.” (EW4: 96-105) His words explained his own reconstruction, why he was leaving the practice of philosophy within the ethos of a Christian community to embrace an effort to reconstruct the secular world with a philosophy of life grounded on scientific principles.

¶20

For an unassuming man, Dewey depicted a remarkable challenge. As an historical advent, pursued for centuries, Christianity had advanced three great ideals: first, “the value, the inalienable worth, of the individual soul,” second, personal participation in a Kingdom of God in which people bound themselves together “in one harmonious whole of sympathy and action;” and third, the revelation of a truth to man that sufficed supreme, without ambiguities, for the guidance of life. Dewey averred that historically Christians had achieved each sufficiently to make them habitual, matters of lip service, and consequently that these great ideals had ceased to work as aspirations. Their redemptive power had thereby disappeared.

¶21

Like many others in his time, Dewey was moving into a secular world. Christianity had become an ineffectual shell, lacking moral force. The material power of science incessantly destabilized a moral order shakily secured by outworn, ineffectual habits. Piecemeal solutions to specific dislocations would not suffice. Science must become a method of truth, not only for the control of the material world, but as “the actual incarnation of truth in human experience and the necessity of giving heed to it.” Remote, merely metaphysical thinking impeded the sound use of scientific method in conducting human affairs. Breaking the ghostly grip on historical life and infusing experience with methods of conduct based on sound science became the mission guiding his work. Reconstruction had to decouple the engine of science from traditional philosophy to enable it guide practical life with tested, instrumental knowledge, or as Dewey put it years later, knowledge which “is instrumental to the enrichment of immediate experience through the control over action that it exercises.”[8]

¶22

On moving to Chicago, Dewey’s life became more thoroughly secular and his commitment to reconstruction filled out conceptually and practically, more actively, on his feet. Dewey worked reflectively and energetically to reconstruct the practice of education. In “My Pedagogic Creed” Dewey closely connected education to reconstructing in both its senses: as a cognitive process, “I believe…, that education must be conceived as a continuing reconstruction of experience; that the process and the goal of education are one and the same thing;” and as a sociocultural program, “I believe that education is a regulation of the process of coming to share in the social consciousness; and that the adjustment of individual activity on the basis of this social consciousness is the only sure method of social reconstruction.” (EW5: 91 & 93)

¶23

Reconstruction rested on education, the existential starting point for all persons, and as Dewey’s summative concern, reconstruction encompassed all of life. An all-encompassing reach distinctively characterized Dewey’s life work, and it derived from his program of reconstruction. Donald F. Koch, editor of Dewey’s class lectures on political philosophy, logic, and ethics, for 1892-1903, treats them all as a massive effort in collaboration with his students to work out the theoretical and practical implications of reconstruction as an intellectual enterprise for the 20th century. (CLJD1)[9] The concept of reconstruction in name and in substance made possible the extraordinary scope of Dewey’s collected writings, an outsized assemblage of books, articles, and other texts subjecting all walks of life to his reconstructive program.

¶24

Beginning with his reading of Comte, ending with his very late writings, reconstruction as a program had a negative and a positive agenda.[10] The negative consisted in Dewey’s efforts to break thought about human conduct free from its roots in the remote, metaphysical systems of prior philosophy. Through Dewey’s negative agenda of reconstruction, he argued strenuously that philosophers should “turn their backs completely” on metaphysical dualisms in the emerging scientific era. (Dewey 2012: 144) And the positive encompassed Dewey’s efforts to ground principles for the rectification of practice in education, public affairs, social, and aesthetic life, which we can loosely sum up as his instrumentalism or experimentalism.

¶25

In what follows, I hypothesize that the trouble with reconstruction arose primarily through Dewey’s pursuit of his negative agenda, an ill-conceived polemic against the historical tradition in philosophy and its implications for education and other humane concerns. To carry out his negative work, Dewey needed to show that prominent thinkers of the past had formulated and propagated unsound ideas, which present-day people should discard or ignore. He tried to do that without engaging the erring ideas at close quarters. His negative agenda became a blanket rejection, leading him to discard much of potential value to his positive agenda. I believe constructive reconstruction—adapting instrumental rationality for the guidance of practical life—also had significant weaknesses, but I will leave the positive agenda and its weaknesses for brief consideration in later sections.

¶26

In the next section, I criticize Dewey’s negative reconstruction by examining some texts that exemplify significant limitations in his historical powers of interpretation. These led to specious judgments and to his throwing out much of potential value to his positive development of instrumental thinking. Then in sections on Kant and Hegel, I suggest that Dewey’s pursuit of his negative agenda in reconstruction weakened his capacity to develop his positive program of reconstruction. If Dewey had worked more assiduously with the intellectual traditions that he declared outmoded and irrelevant, he could have strengthened his own positive vision concerning the value of scientific thinking for the guidance of life. We should learn from the mistakes of the master: I conclude calling for the more robust use of past philosophical and educational thinking, prompting us as contemporary educational theorists to renew our interest in literatures that carry the stigma of Dewey’s declarations of irrelevance.

Reconstruction, Just So

¶27

Can we liken Dewey and Rudyard Kipling? They were contemporaries who led different lives, but both could tell stories, Just so. Kipling gained renown for it—the fanciful tales for his daughter explaining how the leopard got its spots, the camel its hump, the first letter written, and many more.[11] Let’s see about Dewey and the historical judgments on which he based his reconstructive efforts in philosophy, education, and society.

¶28

We’ve seen how Auguste Comte impressed Dewey. Undue individualism destabilized Western society and culture, and thinkers needed to stabilize things by synthesizing science into a positive philosophy of life, a social physics, as Comte called it. Dewey soon found other inspiration, but the intent to rectify historical dislocation by using the potential social significance of science remained the foundation of what Dewey wanted to accomplish. My critique does not primarily contest Dewey’s positive vision. It was what it was. I concentrate on Dewey’s negative agenda, his arguments that past philosophic thought had no value or relevance in guiding present-day life. In many pages of many works, Dewey contended that the thinking of past philosophers imparted concepts, principles, and values inimical to the sound conduct of life in a fully scientific age. Was Dewey’s historical argumentation sound? [12]

¶29

While at Chicago, Dewey’s ideas about reconstruction matured, primarily through his courses and through his practical efforts as an educational reformer. His negative and positive agenda appeared from time to time in essays, but the whole program was developing in a pupal stage. His thought was ripening; his reputation building. To pursue his reconstructive ideas effectively, he needed to write with authority for a readership of significant stature and scope. For a public intellectual, New York provided the best base. Arriving at Columbia in 1905, Dewey began to empower his program. The success, financial and reputational, of Ethics, which Dewey and Tufts published in 1908, added to Dewey’s stature. Then in 1910, he won a lasting readership with How We Think.

¶30

We can take its Chapter 11 as an initial paradigmatic example of negative and positive reconstruction in operation. In it, Dewey contrasted the negative, long-established practices of empirically learning from experience, with the positive practice of scientific method, yet to be applied to ordinary life. He described empirical thinking briefly with no attention to the many different contexts of its use. Then he surveyed three of its characteristic disadvantages and closed reciting the many ways with empirical thinking “subsequent inquiry and reflection are actually stifled.” Dewey immediately turned to a section on “the scientific method,” beginning, of course, “in contrast.” With the ills of mere empiricism left behind, scientific method could ground a sound program for training all in the practice of thinking. (MW6: 296 & Part 3 passim.)

¶31

Dewey had made it as a public intellectual. A string of books followed through the next four decades, all featuring variations on Dewey’s program of reconstruction. The specifics of the problematic varied in the way Dewey stated them, but they all had a negative and positive side, obsolete antecedents that blocked the full emergence of a sound sense of nature and of life within it.[13] Throughout these works, Dewey wrote ex cathedra extensively about his program of reconstruction in philosophy, education, and cultural life. He characterized traditional thinking negatively to delegitimate and suppress metaphysical ideas that he thought were obstructing the emerging efforts to apply to the conduct of life his positive agenda for reconstruction, variously called instrumentalism, empirical naturalism, naturalistic empiricism, experimentalism.

¶32

Reminiscing, Dewey observed that “schematic and formally logical” writing came easily to him, while he found “the concrete, empirical, and ‘practical’” difficult. (LW5: 150) With historical materials, Dewey relied heavily on his facility for schemas, a risky way to write history for it can lead away from the sources, shrouding both the complexity and the substance of past achievements. Dewey had a wealth of synoptic knowledge—general views of the whole, catch phrases about someone’s work, associations between the names of persons and movements linked with diverse labels, keywords, leading ideas, and memes— all packaged for easy apprehension. With a capsule for this, that, and everything, Dewey had a knack for crafting truthy explanations.

¶33

Early on, G. Stanley Hall, a prominent psychologist a generation ahead of Dewey, remarked on a variant prominent in Psychology, where “definitions make the very fiber of the book.”[14] Exploiting his ability to craft general explanations clearly, Dewey wrote an astonishing amount for encyclopedias—Johnson’s Universal Cyclopedia (1894), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology (1902), the Encyclopedia Americana (1904), Monroe’s Cyclopedia of Education (1911-1913), the Encyclopedia and Dictionary of Education (1921), the Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (1933), and the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science (1939).[15] He filled his courses and his books with historical synopses on diverse topics, applying his schemas to them, often highly abstracted from the sources.

¶34

Let’s consider some instances, concentrating on Experience and Nature (1925), for in it he gave a full, typical statement of both his negative and positive agenda of reconstruction and he worried over it to an unusual degree, revising it in 1929 in reaction to its initial reception. To begin, take two sentences from chapter 3 on “Nature, Ends and Histories.” They exemplify Dewey’s historical exposition of past thought at the level of the descriptive sentence: “The doctrine of natural ends was displaced by a doctrine of designs, ends-in-view, conscious aims constructed and entertained in individual minds independent of nature. Descartes, Spinoza and Kant are upon this matter at least in agreement with Bacon, Hume and Helvétius.” (LW1: 81) The six names vaguely concretize “a doctrine of designs, ends-in-view, conscious aims constructed and entertained in individual minds independent of nature,” an abstract construct confected from ungrounded references. The displacing of natural ends by a grab-bag doctrine joins numerous, unspecified texts in evidencing agreement among major thinkers from different times and places about a large, ill-defined transformation of thought. Did the six personages agree? Not impossible, it seems.

¶35

As in other works, here Dewey rarely pointed to specific texts; he gave little context; and he cited almost nothing in explaining his negative and positive agenda for reconstruction. He concatenated capsule descriptions to explain the need for each reconstructive move he had in mind. In this example, the sentences asserting agreement among the six thinkers come from a paragraph of nine such ungrounded assertions about the intellectual effects “in the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century.” A lot happened according to those nine sentences, but other than the six thinkers agreeing on the fate of natural ends, no one did anything. The sentences simply described a lot of abstract transformation having taken place, all in Dewey’s own words without reference to agents, events, contexts, or sources. The chapter included 52 such ungrounded paragraphs. The upshot? “Thus the conception that thought is the final and complete end of nature became a ‘rationalization’ of an existing division of classes in society. The division of men into the thoughtless and the inquiring was taken to be the intrinsic work of nature; in effect it was identical with the division between workers and those enjoying leisure.” [16] Not impossible, it seems. But, how do we know what the chapter concluded? We know it only because Dewey chose to describe it, Just so.

¶36

Alas, Dewey’s schemas, his dropping names, his historical abstractions glibly described, do not empower us as readers to say how we know what we might think we know from what he asserted to have been the case. In interpreting the life experience and the thinking of persons in other times and other places, the historian’s art must give some grounding in actual texts set sufficiently in their context to make an interpretation credible, and to link it and its context to available sources so that others can interpret the matter themselves. One cannot contest points, elaborate them, agree or disagree with closed, encapsulated abstractions, unanchored to particular events that comprised specific actions and actual contexts. The descriptions of traditional thinking and its transformations elicit a shrug, not impossible, it seems, but after a long series of not impossible, it seems, one wonders how the story always turns out, just so.

¶37

In The Quest for Certainty, Dewey similarly dealt with other major thinkers, presenting them through his own unanchored descriptions, without much interpretative context, often as if the ideas deserved no provenance at all. He provided little explication de texte, depicting The Quest at a remarkably high level of generalization. Plato and Aristotle received scattered and conventional mention, as did Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Mill, and Spencer. Dewey wrote about Newton with a little fullness in “Ideas at Work,” and in the “Conflict of Authorities,” he discussed Spinoza some, Kant more, Hegel a bit. But a well-seasoned professor could have written it all consulting no sources. And given such a parsimonious interpretative context, only an equally well-seasoned reader could deal with Dewey’s story on anything other than a take-it or leave-it basis.[17]

¶38

Impersonal abstractions often labeled Dewey’s schemas, not names. Throughout his writing, he often directed his negative reconstruction, at “tradition,” and in The Quest he took it to the extreme. Tradition quested “for certainty,” for “a peace which is assured,” for a stability “fulfilled in pure knowing alone.” Tradition had power: it found “its way into all themes and subjects, and determines the form of current problems and conclusions regarding mind and knowledge.” (LW4: 7) Sometimes Dewey let a particular thinker define tradition, which, as “formulated by Aristotle, ranked social arts lower than pure intellectual inquiry, than knowledge as something not to be put to any use, even a social and moral one.”(LW4: 61) Not impossible, it seems. But did Aristotle really think what Dewey said he thought? And did what Dewey said Aristotle thought really formulate what tradition stood for? Not impossible, it seems. Dewey referred to tradition 145 times in the book: when put together it said that tradition was the recursive sum of what Dewey said it was. Not impossible, it seems….

¶39

Just so. “The whole classic tradition down to our day has continued to hold a slighting view of experience as such, and to hold up as the proper goal and ideal of true knowledge realities which even if they are located in empirical things cannot be known by experimental methods.”(LW4: 22) Not impossible, it seems. Happily, that sclerotic, yet powerful tradition embodied precisely what would enable it to perform its get-lost role assigned to it in Dewey’s program for reconstruction in philosophy. In his view, tradition required the separation of knowing and doing; science could merge them; therefore, contemporary thought could and should jettison tradition. In his turgid prose: “If, accordingly, it can be shown that the actual procedures by which the most authentic and dependable knowledge is attained have completely surrendered the separation of knowing and doing; if it can be shown that overtly executed operations of interaction are requisite to obtain the knowledge called scientific, the chief fortress of the classic philosophical tradition crumbles into dust.” (LW4: 64)Not impossible, it seems, but, oh! Just so!

¶40

Might tradition as a historical concept always encompass complex, multiple ideas and aspirations so different, many-sided, both complementary and discordant, ever in turmoil, so that they keep renewing their potency because no person, group or era, not even Dewey, could encompass them to declare them null and void? That’s not impossible, I say. Exactly so!

¶41

Dewey’s negative agenda for reconstruction set an impossible task, one beyond the limits of historical reason. He devoted great energy to pursuing it unnecessarily. Tradition has no actuality, no power to act. People thinking historically, as Dewey attempted, can only postulate tradition as a noumenal fiction outside the limits of historical experience—exactly the sort of regulative idea that Dewey so railed against in Kant’s ethical thinking. Dewey’s Just So stories, empty negations, could not set the problematic for reconstruction. In pursuing his negative reconstruction Dewey refrained from considering particular texts by particular thinkers written in particular contexts. Without such grounded interpretation, his criticisms had no import other than his ungrounded declarations of opinion. Insofar as he believed those empty opinions, he might have written off potential sources of useful concepts. That’s the rub. Might he have done it differently?

¶42

In 1948 Dewey reintroduced Reconstruction in Philosophy to a mid-century audience. He defended “what one of the milder of my critics has called ‘a sour attitude’ toward the great systems of the past.” Not at all, Dewey chirped. He admired the power and significance of those systems highly “with respect to their connection with intellectual and moral issues of their own time and place.” His doubts concerned only “their relevancy in a much changed human situation,” that is, to the situation of Dewey and friends, to the time and place of contemporary critics. In a new age, antiquarians could amuse themselves with the great systems of yore, but for the conduct of contemporary life those systems sowed dysfunctional confusion, requiring a reconstructive prophylactic ensuring that contact with the source would bear no fruit. (MW12: 257-259)

¶43

Let’s ask, do much changed human situations ipso facto make prior thinking irrelevant? In limiting relevancy, what does Dewey’s phrase, “of their own time and place,” really mean? Weary old Kant had never left Konigsberg. Did his lifespan in that place define his “own time and place?” If the phrase meant the time and place in which a thinker had lived, strictly speaking, say for Plato, it would mean from roughly 400 to 350 BC, primarily Athens and secondarily a few other points of reference in the Peloponnese and the Greek Mediterranean. But would anyone, even Dewey, confine Plato’s time and place so stringently? Well then, how could those later times and other places, each “much changed,” come to hold Plato’s work to be “their own”? Historically powerful ideas exert that power, not only in the time and place of their origin, but in different times and distant places. How does that happen?

¶44

Maybe intellectual habit so extended Plato’s time and place, but not probably, for history tells how the great currency of many thinkers during life evaporated upon their deaths. How does the time of a few persist? Perhaps synoptic history of the sort that Dewey practiced helped other times and other places to make Plato their own. But that would not suffice, for when a time and place have relied on synoptic histories to make foreign thinkers their own, they took over, not vital thought, but the sterile dogmas of an alien occupation.

¶45

Doubtless, Plato’s own time and place extended so far beyond its original Athens because newborn interpreters studied a distant, foreign Plato with care and demonstrated to their time and place why Plato was indeed “their own.” Without renewal by fresh readers, deep readers, the null hypothesis of history holds: the dead have died and life moves on. But where intellectual life is sound, fresh readers continually knead their intellectual resources to draw from them concepts that illuminate the realities of their much-changed circumstances. Was Dewey a fresh reader? Or did his strategy of reconstruction prejudge the irrelevance of prior systems? Did Dewey’s practice of reconstruction in philosophy and education include significant effort to renew works of the past by looking for their potential relevance as a positive resource for addressing the circumstances of his time? Let’s explore this question, looking at what Dewey did, and failed to do, with Kant and Hegel, starting with Kant.

Dewey’s Persistent Kantian Misconstruction

¶46

Throughout, Immanuel Kant served as the bullseye for Dewey’s negative work of reconstruction. In 1924, the New Republic published “Kant after Two Hundred Years,” a prime opportunity for Dewey to rethink his view of Kant. Instead, he wrote a grudging appreciation, reiterating why Kant made reconstruction so necessary. “This was his great achievement: demarcation of two realms, one of mechanical science, the other of moral freedom and faith, connected yet independent, one beginning at the boundaries of the other.” Kant’s net influence surrendered “the concrete world of affairs to the domain of mechanism fatalistically understood.” It shed “over a life built out of mechanical subordinations the aureole of a superworldly ideal, sentimental at best, fanatical and deadly at worst.” (MW15: 310 & 312)

¶47

We could here worry over Dewey’s 1915 lectures on German Philosophy and Politics, which his 1924 assessment of Kant reprised in brief. But we would distract ourselves from the most interesting question by trying to unravel how passions of war skewed Dewey’s assessments as he tried to anathematize Kant, Fichte, Hegel and others for disposing Germans to aggressive self-assertion.[18] So too, Dewey’s extensive engagement with Kant’s ethical thought should not detain us. The two editions of Ethics with James H. Tufts, the several iterations of extensive syllabuses for his ethics courses, and summative articles on ethics and moral thought constituted a major accomplishment, but a specialized history conventionally told, largely independent of Dewey’s reconstructive program.[19]

¶48

Let’s also pass quickly by what Dewey had to say about Kant in his 1888 book on Leibniz’s New Essays, noting only that it reinforced his idea that Kant stood as the great defender of the rationalist dualism that so needed reconstruction. Let’s take as our starting point that Kant served as the prime target for Dewey in his negative program for reconstruction.[20] Let’s ask, why? Why did Dewey assign Kant that role? Dewey’s reading of Kant presents an interesting, but problematic paradox.

¶49

Kant’s critical philosophizing, initiated by his three Critiques, made human experience in its different forms central to his philosophic inquiry. Kant has exerted substantial historical influence because numerous subsequent thinkers have widely extended this initiative by centering concern on experience in different lifeworlds. Kant’s question—How is experience possible?—has become the great heuristic for post-Kantian inquiry. Given the centrality of experience in Dewey’s thought, he appears to participate significantly in this movement of post-Kantian inquiry. Yet in writing about Kant, Dewey did not recognize the centrality of experience in Kant’s Critiques, nor did he profit from the way Kant inquired into the possibility of experience to the degree that other thinkers of his time were doing.

¶50

Of course, Dewey knew that “possible experience” had a role in The Critique of Pure Reason, less so with the other two critiques. But Dewey said little about how Kant examined the possibility of experience, an important strategy of inquiry for Kant. In “Kant and Philosophic Method” (1884), an essay from his student days, Dewey noted that Kant added to rationalism and empiricism a further method in philosophy, examining the possibility of experience. Dewey quickly declared it “doubly false” and in the closing third turned to the promise of Hegel’s logic, use of negation, and dialectic as a more promising path to sound method. (EW1: 34-47) Inquiry about the possibility of experience thereupon dropped out of Dewey’s understanding of Kant’s philosophic effort.

¶51

Through his docility, his penchant for absorbing the conventional ethos surrounding him, at Hopkins and Michigan Dewey absorbed an understanding of Kant’s critical philosophy that he never outgrew.[21] He did not become infatuated with Kant, as he did with Hegel, but he internalized a particular understanding of the strategic role Kant had in the history of philosophy, which he maintained through his whole career. Dewey formed his estimate of Kant’s critical philosophy through his earliest mentor, H. A. P. Torrey, and then through George Morris, especially Morris’s study of the Kant’s first critique[22] and Edward Caird’s impressive Critical Account of the Philosophy of Kant. Then in 1890, that estimate became fixed as Dewey prepared his enthusiastic review of Caird’s more recent, 2-volume analysis of Kant’s critical philosophy.[23] That basically completed Dewey’s grounding in Kant as the initiator of critical philosophy.[24]

¶52

Let’s grasp the philosophical context and Kant’s place in it as it would have appeared to Dewey’s mentors in the 1880s and 90s. To do so, I will first set the scene, reminding ourselves that the emerging academic world of secular scholarship and instruction was not yet the prevailing ethos. Dewey, formed in the old world, participated in the emergence of the new, carrying with him vestiges of the old, among them his understanding of Kant. That had consequences for the character of Dewey’s mature work. To make those clear, I will tell my own Just so story, not to explicate Kant, but to illuminate some problematic aspects of Dewey’s thought.[25]

¶53

In the United States, and Britain too, both the old-time colleges and even the emerging universities still invested philosophy with strong, religious expectations. Torrey, Morris, and Caird wrote thoughtfully as concerned Christians, nervously drawn to Kant as a thinker who, from within their religious ethos, took on the intellectual challenges to it, perhaps risking too much in seeking to achieve too much. Until Dewey went to Chicago, he worked within the Christian academic climate. We think of Johns Hopkins as the first modern, graduate university in America, but Dewey’s Hopkins fully participated in the old-time ethos. It had deep roots.[26]

¶54

Kant succeeded as the first philosopher of front rank to live and work as a university professor. Up to that time, as Kant himself noted in Der Streit der Facultäten, the philosophy faculty was decidedly a junior faculty to those for Medicine, Law, and Theology. (Kant, 1798) Kant turned from a clerical career only at the end of his studies;[27] Schelling and Hegel, with their friend, the poet, Hölderlin, studied theology together at the University of Tübingen;[28] Marx studied law;[29] and even Nietzsche slid into classical studies, with some philosophy mixed in, having started preparing for the clergy.[30] Through most of the 19th century, a person acquired an academic grounding in philosophy in preparing for the law or the clergy.

¶55

Most systematic philosophy, whether rationalist or empiricist, came from outside the university, and academic philosophers had responsibility to defend and disseminate a religiously sound philosophic grounding.[31] When Hume raised Kant from his dogmatic slumber, the alarm was not simply an interesting argument about causality, but one widely perceived as shaking the foundation of religiously sound philosophic syntheses. If causality merely signified an habitual expectation between something that seems frequently to follow another, that raised troubling questions about the relation between humans and divinity. Thus, expectations then associated with his academic role constrained Kant, yet at the same time, he was a man deeply moved by enlightenment aspirations.[32]

¶56

However staid in his ways Kant may have been, he had an active spirit and curiosity, an openness to advanced ideas. He might well have felt in sympathy with Hume, but he could not have expressed that directly from his position. He took over a decade to work out a finely tuned response to Hume. It did not directly contest Hume’s arguments on their own ground, but significantly shifted how thinkers could discuss matters like causality, the questions that might destabilize the philosophic grounding for religious thought. Kant initiated what people quickly started calling critical philosophy, newly distinct from the prior mode, which aimed at a positive metaphysics. Kant did something both simple and radical: he changed the basic question generating philosophic thinking. His strategy evoked considerable angst among strongly religious thinkers, however, for he ceded a lot of ground to thinkers such as Hume.

¶57

Let us try to feel the angst, Just so. Up through Kant’s pre-critical period, what he and others wondered about as they reflected in wonder, were variations on the question, “I wonder what X is?” What is being? What is God? What is truth? What is knowledge? What is real? What is matter? What is duty? What is beauty? What is causality? It seemed however that for every claim about what X is, a critic would pop up showing the claim was unsound, an erudite whack-a-mole routine. Kant said in effect, “OK. If we keep deceiving ourselves in asking what X is, let’s try asking, How is X possible?” Critical philosophy would stop trying to account for the existence of things and would attend to their possibility, taking their existence as an evident given. Kant did not ask, What is experience? He asked, How is experience possible? He worked The Critique of Pure Reason out by asking how experience of the external world was possible. He generated The Critique of Practical Reason by inquiring how our acting on the ground of principle alone was possible. He thought through The Critique of the Power of Judgment by exploring how judgments of taste and purposeful actions were possible.

¶58

How did the what-is-X question, and our world is still full of them, differ from the how-is-X-possible question? Kant changed the standpoint from which he posed the question. The old-time philosopher asked the what-is-X question from the standpoint of the X, what is X in itself, what is it really, truly, essentially, actually, independent of us? The Kantian philosopher asked the how-is-X-possible question for him, from his own standpoint, how is the X, which happens in my world all the time, possible for me? How come it can happen? Instead of inquiring into existence or being, the Kantian philosopher inquired as an agent how a given matter or concern was a possibility for him.

¶59

We are seeking to understand why Dewey may have failed to appreciate critical philosophy as a means of investigating experience. To do so we need to grasp how historical change can include a shift in the prevailing ethos, which can deeply alter historical experience, rather like the famous “duck or rabbit” image associated with Gestalt psychology. With a complex work such as the Critique of Pure Reason subtle shifts in the prevailing historical ethos can lead to significant shifts in how people interpret the work.

¶60

Until Dewey moved to Chicago at the age of 35, he had lived and worked in a Christian academic ethos in which the metaphysical concerns of the Critique were dominant. Interpreters paid less attention to the basic question of critical philosophy and worried instead whether Kant had soundly deduced the logical necessity of the categories with which people constructed possible experience. They further attached considerable significance to his distinction between phenomena, the world of ordinary experience, and noumena, regulative ideas referring to a fictitious thing-in-itself, outside the limits of possible experience. The Kant that Dewey internalized between 1880 and 1894 was this Kant, especially as interpreted by Morris and Caird. It was not the Kant of critical philosophy, but Kant, the last great defender of metaphysical thought.[33]

¶61

As the 20th century loomed, academic thinking rapidly became more secular, and significant changes altered the perception of works like Kant’s Critiques. Rigorously deducing the necessity of the categories lost importance.[34] Their existential ineluctability sufficed: “assailed by eyes, ears, nose, skin, and entrails at once,” thrust into this life, each “feels it all as one great blooming, buzzing confusion,” as William James observed.[35] The construction of possible experience followed. The secular academic ethos has been inherently existential and anti-metaphysical. In that ethos, Kant’s introductory sections on asking how experience was possible received more attention. So too did a short aesthetic, in which the experiencer acquires through space and time the inchoate contents that will become constructed through categories into substantive experience. And then a longer section on principles, about how active agents use concepts to construct and control, as best they can, their experience in the world, finally gained primacy. The new Critique became much simplified, a strategic asset for many innovative strands of 20th-century inquiry—within philosophy and in other subjects like psychology, ethology, physics, sociology, etc.

¶62

As Dewey went off to Chicago, he consciously left a Christian academic ethos for a more secular one and he could perfectly well have become a twentieth-century post-Kantian. He might have reread Kant’s first critique. He would have passed over the deduction of the categories, thinking it didn’t matter so much, recognizing the existential necessity of living with and through the categories, ambulando as he would put it. He would feel comfortable within the limits of experience as the long last half, the dialectic, laid them out, and he would have shrugged at the noumenon, saying he could have regulative principles just as well without it. He might even have mined parts, like the third analogy of experience, on the principle of community or reciprocity, which would have helped him develop his ideas about the organic circuit more fully. But Dewey could not read Kant in this way. By that time, committed to the negative side of reconstruction, he stubbornly maintained the nineteenth-century idea of Kant as the man who upheld the authority of an other-worldly metaphysics. As such, Dewey’s Kant ceased to be a great defender, becoming the man who had peddled rigorous deductions and a mysterious thing-in-itself to his teachers.[36] Not seeing the new Kant ironically left Dewey unable to respond to many developments taking place that would have strengthened his ideas.

¶63

Let’s briefly sum up discussing Kant as a potential resource that Dewey ignored by noting two major consequences of Dewey’s inability to engage in a fresh reading of Kant. The two were distinct, but converged, and had much to do with aspects of Dewey’s thinking that have attracted criticism during and after his mature career. One concerned his instrumentalism, but I will postpone the instrumental until after discussing Hegel in relation to Dewey’s critique of the great systems. The other consequence concerned Dewey’s central concept of experience, and related concepts such as education, nature, art—the big ideas he sought to reconstruct. Dewey habitually hypostatized such abstract concepts, still bent on asking the what-is-X question. More attention to Kant’s critical philosophy could have helped him control this habit.

¶64

Dewey generally wrote about vital processes as if he knew what they were. “Experience is….” “Education is….” “Art is ….”[37] Dewey argued against metaphysical thinking, but he characteristically wrote with a metaphysical diction. Definitions of abstract processes and conceptual things fill his work. In reviewing Experience and Nature, George Santayana criticized Dewey for forgetting that experience as such required an experiencing agent to give it a form—to determine its beginning, middle, and end, which Santayana called the foreground of experience. Dewey ignored the foreground, the agent for whom experience becomes possible. For Santayana, the experiencer preceded experience, immersed in circumstances, the phenomenal sources of the experience. We might say that we should use the concept of “experience”, and other concepts for active processes, as verbs, not nouns, as actions, not substantives. An agent, involved in action, constructs experience in time, with a beginning, middle, and end, which are given, not intrinsically by experience, but as characteristics of the construction by the agent.

¶65

Santayana observed: “Its name is Experience; but lest we should misunderstand this ambiguous word, it is necessary to keep in mind that in [Dewey’s] system experience is impersonal. It is not, as a literary psychologist might suppose, a man's feelings and ideas forming a life-long soliloquy, his impressions of travel in this world. Nor is it, as a biologist might expect, such contact of sensitive animals with their environment as adapts them to it and teaches them to remember it. No: experience is here taken in a transcendental, or rather in a moral, sense, as something romantically absolute and practically coercive.”[38]

¶66

Dewey replied in “Half-Hearted Naturalism” (LW3:73-81), talking around Santayana’s point. We might make criticisms like Santayana’s about Art as Experience, for experience comes across in the same way. “Experience,” almost always used as a noun, would denote an abstract process with a blurred locus of control. A contemporary reading of Kant would have greatly helped keep track of the agents working the processes about which Dewey wrote.

¶67

At this point, let us turn away from Kant in considering the negative side of Dewey’s effort at reconstruction in philosophy and education. Kant will return, but first we should recognize that he presents too easy a foil for suggesting that Dewey’s negativity towards past thinkers deprived him of important intellectual resources. Dewey engaged Kant in an atmosphere of enthusiasm for Hegel, making it unlikely he would deal positively with Kant’s work. From early on, he distrusted Kant’s thought and seems to have read it from duty, not choice. Hegel was a different matter. Many who are deeply versed in Dewey’s thought suggest that in spite of his rejection of past systems, Dewey made Hegel’s thinking a positive resource, malgré lui. Let’s test that out.

Woozling in Reverse[39]

¶68

Remember in Winnie-the-Pooh how Pooh and Piglet pursue the Woozle in the snow, round and round the larch trees, ever surer they would catch one, for they kept seeing the tracks of more and more Woozles. Only problem: the tracks in the snow were really their own. Publication of a text from Dewey’s 1897 course on “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” (CLJD1: 333-405) has set off a Woozle hunt for Dewey’s “permanent Hegelian deposit,” possibly even for a fresh reading of Hegel by the master himself. A growing group of scholars are finding similarities between Dewey’s later work and things they attribute to that early course, namely an au currant humanist/historicist Hegel, the human spirit forming itself through the personal experience of each and the historical experience of all. Only problem: the scholars, not Dewey, make the connections between the 1897 course and Dewey’s later work. The hunters demonstrate the enduring influence of his early engagement with Hegel by reading their interpretation of Hegel into the content and expression of Dewey’s later work, and into the mysterious text of 1897, too. By doing so, they open new lines of interpretation and further inflate Dewey’s prestige as a man of vision, who anticipated the most recent interpretations of an obscure yet seminal thinker.

¶69

And they sight some big tracks, indeed: “in Hegel’s terms, when Dewey reflects on the psychology of individual humans, in works such as Human Nature and Conduct, he articulates a philosophy of subjective spirit; when he reflects on the history of Western civilization, in works such as Reconstruction in Philosophy and The Quest for Certainty, he develops a philosophy of objective spirit.”[40] The hunters, surely by inadvertence, could even suggest an astonishing reverse causation: “Hegel’s reflections on language are remarkably similar to Dewey’s.”[41]

¶70

But let’s not be too hard on the Woozle hunters. Their hunt pursues a hypothesis: Dewey’s early reading in and about German idealism—first Kant, then neo-Hegelians of his time, and finally Hegel himself—left an imprint that helped him to shape, and us to understand, his intellectual development and his more mature work on logic, psychology, social thought, pedagogy, and even theology. John R. Shook started things off with his Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality,[42] and James A. Good followed with an even fuller effort in A Search for Unity in Diversity. He surveyed recent Hegel scholarship in English well and described Anglo-American Hegelianism until about 1900. Then in three chapters, he examined Dewey’s education and professional formation prior to moving to Columbia in 1904.[43] Numerous other scholars have joined the hunt, finding further Hegelian ideas in Dewey’s later work.[44] Most recently, James Scott Johnston has convincingly reinterpreted Dewey’s intellectual development in John Dewey's Earlier Logical Theory, shifting the question somewhat away from Hegel’s influence towards the immanent development of Dewey’s early ideas about logic, which derived significantly from Hegel.[45]

¶71

All this work exemplifies the reputational inflation that clouds our judgment of Dewey. To grasp what’s happened, let’s think of Andersen’s weavers, not as actual swindlers—nothing like that is going on—but as personifications of our proclivity to magnify reality. Nice phrases stick in the mind, like Dewey’s “permanent Hegelian deposit.” But when assayed in Dewey’s Collected Works, the lode offers little worth mining. Before attention turned to Dewey’s text on Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit, the documentary basis for understanding his engagement with the work of Hegel seemed relatively thin.[46] Prior to 1889, Dewey clearly developed a well-formed Hegelian framework with little direct study of Hegel’s own writings;[47] between 1890 and 1892 Dewey worked intensively on Hegel, dealing with his work directly in his teaching and writing;[48] and after 1892 Dewey seemed to sense that Hegel had become a spent force in his creative thinking and he began to pursue the negative and positive sides of his agenda for reconstruction.[49]

¶72

Around the turn of the 21sth century, scholars got access through publication of his class lectures to “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit.” (CLJD1: 332-400) The text seemed to augment the resources for understanding Dewey’s appropriation of Hegel’s thought greatly. Then and now scholars have concentrated on Hegel’s ideas about spirit, Geist, and an 85-page text by Dewey on Hegel’s philosophy of spirit made the permanent deposit vastly more attractive to Dewey’s interpreters. We should hypothesize that in the excitement the 1897 text did not receive sufficiently rigorous critical examination.

¶73

Too long for the text of a lecture, the document has none of the breaks expected in a compilation of student class notes.[50] The initial 35 paragraphs provide some biographical framework and some exploration of Hegel’s thinking. It gives some detail on his early religious writings from when he worked in isolation as a Hauslehrer. A survey of Hegel’s thinking as it stood, circa 1800, followed, including a standard survey of Hegel’s antecedents, outlining the succession of Kant, Fichte, and Schelling. The next three paragraphs rush Hegel from 1800 to 1817, when he published his Philosophie des Geistes, the third volume of his Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften. In all, the introductory paragraphs relied on thoroughly conventional resources, Edward Caird’s Hegel (1883) and Karl Rosenkranz’s Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegels Leben (1844), the one a 220-page introduction to Hegel’s thought, and the other the favorable biography, as distinct from the hostile one, of the two biographies then available.[51]

¶74

Textual criticism needs to concentrate on the remaining four-fifths of the document. To the textual critic, these paragraphs pose an alternative: they document either Dewey’s considered reflection and commentary with Hegel’s Philosophie des Geistes as foil or they primarily condense Hegel’s book, converting the 386-page Philosophie des Geistes into a 60-page English précis with a few interpolations, usually clarifying what a reader at the end of the 19th century might find especially obscure in the original. The Woozlers have taken the first option up with alacrity.[52] I believe the second stands up on a close comparison of the 119 paragraphs from 1897 with the full text of Hegel’s Philosophie des Geistes.[53]

¶75

When all is said and done, we should conclude that the German 1845 edition of Philosophie des Geistes served as the source for most of what the concluding 119 paragraphs contain. Further, Dewey prepared the précis, and the material introductory to it, for the spring 1891 course on “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” at Michigan.[54] In substance, the précis does not give grounds for attributing to Dewey a present-day humanist/historicist reading of Hegel. Comparing it to Hegel’s text, substantive weaknesses in the précis become apparent.[55] They draw attention to the second concern I mentioned in introducing “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit,” namely an effort to estimate what Dewey did not get from Hegel’s Philosophie des Geistes that would have been of use in developing his own ideas. Rather than build a tenuous case that Dewey had a present-day interpretation of Hegel tucked away as his permanent deposit, let’s use “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” to see what Dewey did not get that might have been of value to him.

¶76

Recent interpretations of Hegel pay close attention to how Hegel developed his thinking from 1800 through 1807, working with Schelling and then alone, creating the Phänomenologie des Geistes as the great Bildungsroman of the human spirit.[56] Introductory sections of “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” merely mentioned the Jena years and the Phänomenologie des Geistes in passing, concentrating instead on Hegel’s prior religious writings. This weighting in the introductory part does not suggest a Deweyan breakthrough in interpreting Hegel.[57] The Philosophie des Geistes did include, however, a substantial section on “phenomenology.”

¶77

In it, Hegel reprised the much larger Phänomenologie, describing the experience of Geist in ways particularly rich with concepts important in present-day readings of his work. This mini phenomenology explained the self-transformation of Geist from naïve consciousness to self-consciousness to reason, not talking about it from the outside, but trying to communicate how Geist internally experienced those changes as it carried them out as their active agent. Paragraphs 75 through 85 in the précis condense this section in Hegel’s original, paragraphs 413 through 439.[58] Let’s look closely at how the précis condensed these 30 pages into 7 to see what Dewey missed that might have served his later work.

¶78

Hegel came of age and developed as a philosopher mulling Kant’s great question, how is experience possible? Kant had answered abstractly. He used logical categories to show how reason could construct experience by forming the inchoate data we sense into the phenomenal world we experience. Could reason really do that? We have seen that Kant tried to give a deductive answer to demonstrate that indeed reason could use abstract categories in this way. But peers, prominently Hegel (with the young Dewey in his train), thought this deductive demonstration might be sound in principle, but an answer itself rather empty of experience. Hegel wanted to see the construction of experience taking place in substantive human experience. If experience became possible by constructing it from data and the conceptual categories, a philosopher should be able to see the whole process happening in the course of life, the life of persons and the historical life of humanity as a whole. Hegel’s great project became phenomenology, the study of phenomena in the making, of the self-construction of all the various kinds of experiencing in human life as it happened.[59]

¶79

Hegel is difficult to read, here and throughout, because he took on a difficult task, wanting to grasp clearly the experience of constructing experience, to do it as it happened. Kant’s excessive abstraction arose because he had simply reverse-engineered “pure reason”—reason rein, clean and simple reason; reason thinking that X is Y, that A causes B, that C and D are interacting together. Examining “pure reason,” Kant arrived at a solution implicit in his starting point. Instead, Hegel wanted to start with an indeterminate constructor, one that could start from nothing and make experience possible from there.

¶80

Hegel began with Geist, sometimes wrongly translated as mind, more properly as spirit. It helps to remember that the German Geist and the English ghost are the same word, which originally meant “the soul or spirit, as the principle of life; also [the] ghost of life [as in the phrase,] ‘to give up the ghost’: to breathe one's last, expire, die.” For Hegel, Geist indicated a human agency potentially capable of forming itself. Hegelian phenomenology would study Geist forming its capacities for experience in concrete personal life and in collective historical life. Hegel differentiated phenomenology from philosophy, using phenomenology to depict how Geist experientially formed and brought itself to life while confining philosophy to surveying the formed results as Geist had up to then realized them in the philosopher’s present and the culture of her time.

¶81

Phenomenology followed how Geist, the human spirit incarnate in each of us and in all of us, existentially created our capacities for experience, understanding it as a protean, active agent coming in life to take care for itself in every way that humans do. He presented it sometimes as Geist looking subjectively on the world and sometimes objectively, appearing for us to be in the world. In this effort, Hegel would use simple terms for this Geist like das Ich, the I, instead of abstract ones like the Ego, and direction signals like an sich, in oneself, and für sich, for itself, to indicate switches between internal and external perspectives. Hegel also paid much attention in his thinking, and in the existential self-formation of Geist, to the formation (Bildung) of important concepts (Begriffe), that is, to Begriffsbildung, concept formation, putting the two concepts together as often happens in German. And Begriffe, concepts, were not for Hegel inert thoughts or empty logical operations, but intellectual tools with which we can say, “I grasped what happened;” “Ich griff was passiert.”[60]

¶82

Hegel worked as a critical philosopher in the spirit of Kant, asking not what X is, but how is X possible. Hence, for Hegel observing what Geist did had less importance than grasping how Geist did it. How is self-formation possible? To respond, Hegel used a concept of great importance for his thinking. Throughout his writing, he extensively used the noun, Aufhebung, and the verb, aufheben, a very old word with an active, hard-working meaning. It has a nutty translation—“to sublate, sublation,” as if any English speaker would intuit what that means. Discontented with obscure, Latinate terms, translators often talked around Geist experiencing Aufhebungen, and their doing so made the actual working of Hegel’s dialectic seem complicated or formalistic. We should not translate the noun, Aufhebung, and the verb, aufheben. We should use their English cognates, upheaval and heave up. For Hegel, Geist heaves itself up from one of its possibilities to another. Geist follows one line of self-formation until evident tensions and stirrings for it make another line of self-formation discernable, and grasping it, Geist wrenches itself from the established path and heaves itself onto the new one, taking with it all the capacities for experience it had previously formed.[61]

¶83

In the labors of life from time immemorial, people have heaved things up, out, on, aside—say fallen forest limbs up onto a pile of firewood for winter warmth or stones from a field being plowed to build a wall or a home. In birth itself, through excruciating labor, the newborn is heaved into the world, drawing a first breath of life, a novel Geist forming-itself thereafter, heaving itself up from possibility to possibility. The heaving up cancels the prior state but substantially preserves the wood, the stone, the parental genes and genius, as something new takes on new form and new uses. Geist forms itself through such upheavals, which in the fullness of history take infinitely varied forms. Hegel used variants of aufheben, and of the closely related erheben, to denote the Begriff that was the workhorse of his thinking. Through the section on “Phenomenology” in the Philosophie des Geistes, Hegel described how Geist moved itself through a series of Aufhebungen, heaving itself up from naïve awareness into controlling its sense perceptions and initiating systematic understanding and then heaving itself through yet another Aufhebung into self-consciousness.

¶84

Hegel’s first five paragraphs of the section on “Phenomenology,” surveyed what Geist must to do to heave itself up into a state of reason, the formative agenda of the whole section. Then Hegel went back to its beginning and explained how Geist moved itself through key states of consciousness to throw itself into a state of self-consciousness. After it has made each move, Geist sees that each heave has made sense, but making the heave was contingent and difficult, sometimes dangerous and painful. The Deweyan précis covered what Geist did but diffused the agency of Geist, dropping out the difficulty and risk, describing it as something that simply happened. For instance, the précis summarized the Aufhebungen through which consciousness readies itself for self-consciousness by reporting the results in four packets, each beginning “it is discovered that….” (¶79 summarizing ¶¶418-423) Thus readers get a series of outcomes to actions by a vague agent they cannot grasp.

¶85

For Hegel, the difficulty and risk that Geist faced in moving itself from desire to reason involved Anerkennen, the Begriff denoting the process that takes place as a self-aware, desiring agent encounters another self-aware, desiring agent. Hegel had prepared the way with several paragraphs on how self-conscious desire initially leads Geist to consume into itself what is not itself, the object of its self-aware desire, to eat, to drink, to nourish the self. This desire, felt as a drive to take possession, motivates the life and death struggle that erupts when two self-aware agents encounter each other. When an I, knowing only desire, encounters a different I driven too by desire, each sees the other as an object to be possessed, consumed as one’s own. Both enter compulsively into a struggle to death, until one, on the brink, desists, choosing in defeat life over death, recognizing—acknowledging, honoring, respecting—the other as a self-aware I, driven by a desire like its own. Unlike the contract theorists, who superficially conceived an originating conflict and a facile, prudential contract resulting from it,[62] Hegel deeply probed the struggle culminating in a recognition, affirming life in the face of death. It issued eventually, not in a contract, but in each reciprocally recognizing the other and oneself as autonomous, self-aware beings. Geist could base many different bonds upon that recognition.[63]

¶86

Hegel took 10 pages to show this struggle unfolding fully and to probe its consequences and implications. The précis compressed those into a bit more than one page, dropping out a great deal. The précis summed up what happened with an abbreviated discussion of two selves recognizing each other by stating that “full freedom is developed when the particular selves recognize that there is a true unity of will to which all equally owe obedience.” (¶85) The quotation formally states the result of the recognizing process, but the human experiencing of the process would be of greater interest to the humanist/historicist Hegel, and Hegel explored it in some detail in the original. In the précis, the reciprocal dynamic requisite in two persons recognizing one another became converted immediately into a condition of unity, putting philosophy before phenomenology.

¶87

The précis confused the Hegelian struggle that erupts when two primordially self-conscious persons encounter one another with the Hobbesian war of each against all. It held further that through the struggle that stops just short of death, the victor, the evident master, achieved recognition, for he “learns that he must not destroy others but that he must care for them in order to be cared for himself. He recognizes, that is, that his free existence is dependent upon the existence of others and is not in hostility to other existences.” (¶85) Edifying pabulum! For Hegel, the struggle left the victor in his Trumpian ignorance, supposedly superior but bereft of recognition by the loser, whom the victor could neither fathom nor trust. The slave had ironically become the free man, able to both see himself as himself and as the master saw him. The master, alone with his mastery, could only do that by renouncing his mastery, recognizing the other, not as the slave, but the free man, a peer, who now stood before him.

¶88

Early and late, Dewey passed over a lot in Hegel’s thought that might have helped him develop his positive goals. The précis compressed a text in which Geist repeatedly heaved itself up into new frameworks, unleashing new forms of activation for itself while preserving what in substance it previously had made of itself. Dewey’s Collected Writings show no sign that he tarried with the concept of aufheben and incorporated it into his mode of understanding human action. Variants of the term, either as sublation or aufheben, do not occur in its many volumes. Using plain English, Dewey once noted how readers might heave a sigh of relief, and he referred on occasion to upheavals as historic events like the Russian Revolution. Although Hegel’s ghost might refer to those as Aufhebungen, Dewey’s usage did not signal his adoption of Hegelian concepts here. Had he done so, Dewey might have practiced his program of reconstruction more effectively, but he did not do so.

¶89

To approach a close, we can only think suggestively about what Dewey did not get from Hegel, or from Kant, or many others, that might have empowered his aspirations. Importantly, had Dewey taken more from Hegel, he might not have developed that sour attitude towards past thought that one of his critics remarked upon. In his writing, Dewey concentrated quite hard on both personal development and historical change, but what he says about them frankly does not excite much interest because Dewey omitted what Santayana called the foreground of all the experience, its contingency in time and space for the agent constructing it. In contrast, Hegel crafted his concepts to grasp that contingency, Protean change through experience, historical and personal.

¶90

With more attention to Hegel’s account of how spirit opens new paths from the internal tensions in past achievements Dewey might have had a different way to deal with all those dualisms with which he warred. Aufhebungen also might have provided a better way to think about the formative experience that the young unfold for themselves than Dewey’s description of it as a process of continuous growth, which glossed over its inner working with a softly padded outer cover. Dewey could also have done more with the problem of recognition, Anerkennen, to resist the impersonalizing forces, powerful in his world and ours. Modern schooling, even schooling pervaded by Deweyan principles, all too often fails to support the efforts of those who toil within it to achieve meaningful recognition, Anerkennen of self and other. And finally, Dewey showed few signs that he considered Begriffsbildung, concept formation, as a potential alternative to his obsession with method in thinking about how scientists proceed in advancing their work and understanding.

¶91

Suffice it for now, to wrap Hegel up. The 1897 course really was an 1891 course. The vast bulk of substantive documentation for Dewey on Hegel comes from that earlier date. Early in 1891, in an expression of his reconstructive program, Dewey clearly drew a line between Kant and Hegel, judging Hegel’s thought to be in substance on the side of the reconstructors: “I conceive Hegel—entirely apart from the value of any special results—to represent the quintessence of the scientific spirit.” But he foresaw a problem, too, continuing to note that the state of science had been such that “Hegel’s standpoint was, therefore of necessity obscure.” (EW3: 134-141, quotations: 138 & 140) In 1891 Dewey hoped that he might overcome that obscurity, but quickly an increasingly mute record suggests subsequent experience was disabusing him of that hope.[64]

¶92

That Dewey continued for a time to give his course on Hegel’s Logic and on the Philosophy of Spirit tells us little—we all have taught topics after our flush excitement for them has waned. In Democracy and Education (EW9: 62-5), in Reconstruction (MW12: 90, 140, 157), and in The Quest (LW4: 50-52), Dewey clearly put Hegel among the bad guys in need of reconstruction. During the two big wars, Dewey showed little compunction in including Hegel among those to blame for German transgressions. (MW8: 184-200 & 421-442; MW10: 221-226) Did Dewey need to target Hegel in his work at reconstruction? Did he need to uncouple from earlier thinkers to make the case for his present views? By doing so, did he diminish his own intellectual resources for putting forward his positive philosophy?

¶93

I think Dewey’s negative agenda of reconstruction had neither substance nor purpose. He could have advanced his positive agenda just as well without it and by pursuing negative he channeled his energy into a sinkhole and impoverished the background from which he could draw in developing his actual achievements.

Envoi

¶94

Let’s back away a bit from both Hegel and Kant, and think in conclusion about Dewey’s view of history. Dewey treated historical life in a deeply reductionist way. To begin, he schematized it, reducing the record to a few names, keywords, associations, memes, and conventional capsulations. Then he configured all that into a single great problem, both enduring and pernicious, the split between intellectual life and material life, and he took the reconciliation of that split as the grail of his quest. Dewey’s reductionist history diluted what it preserved and consigned to oblivion what his schemas did not catch. Does historical life really involve a split between matter and mind? Not if historical life involves living agents acting in a world thinking about what they do.

¶95

“Those who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat it.”[65] Let’s think briefly as critical philosophers about Santayana’s famous dictum, asking, how is historical life possible? For someone living in a human world, it is not only the categories of Kantian logic that make experience possible. All sorts of acquired concepts, tools, principles, routines, regulations, laws, ideas, compacts, practices, tastes, skills, desires, works of art and literature, and so much more, serve in making experience possible in its full human complexity. The wondrously rich past, all the available culture, both high and popular, stands prior to present experience and it always will. Relative to possible experience, history stands as an array of a priori synthetic resources for the construction of experience in the living present.[66] Why rail against it? Why desiccate it in empty schemas?

¶96

Let us entertain the possibility that positively bad ideas are very rare and that historical change does not convert sound thinking achieved in former times into a set of erroneous propositions. Error puts thought out of context. Context binds thought and historical change alters contexts. Without care about who is doing what and why, thought easily stagnates and people apply ideas out of context. That is why I have been harping on the importance of remaining clear about agency, suspicious that Dewey did not maintain clarity about who was acting with various ideas for what purposes.

¶97

To see what I mean, reflect on the list of dualisms that Dewey worried over in Democracy and Education. The list in his original index was long, over 30 pairs: activity and knowledge, activity vs. mind, authority vs. freedom, and so on. Each part of each dualism stands on its own as a legitimate topic in education. Take out the conjunctions, the versuses! Dewey linked them together as apparent dualisms that he could dispense with. Separately, even paired, these concepts posed no problem in their proper contexts. Changed conditions posed the problem. Changed conditions altered the contexts in which people used powerful concepts, altering who tried to do what with them for what reasons, inviting the inappropriate use of the ideas.[67] Let’s see how new conditions altered agency, shifting who would use the concepts in what ways.

¶98

Once upon a time, the agent of education was the infant, the child, the youth, the man and woman, and if we stop ourselves, that is still sort-of true, perhaps even more than sort-of. But Dewey was writing in a time when “education” was rapidly becoming institutionalized, writing explicitly for prospective normal school teachers. With these historical changes, the agent of education ceased to be the person engaged in an effort at lifelong self-formation. It shifted to the institutions that the public powers were everywhere creating with the purpose of educating the young and even the mature. Hence, education has become what schools do.

¶99

Dewey participated in this displacement that was occurring through the institutionalization of education—perhaps reluctantly, perhaps by inadvertence.[68] We respond to his pedagogy because he seems to have wanted to preserve the agency of the child and the person in their educational experience. But he muddled it. He liked to blur his prose, and “education” became a metaphysical blob, a subtype of Dewey’s “experience” both actions without agents. A new context—institutional programs, programs in which normal school teachers would be functionaries—would alter who would use the concepts for what purpose. Concepts formerly of use to the agents of education, would become potential principles controlling activities by those acting impersonally in support of the educative agents, an open invitation for the concepts to regulate activities inappropriately.

¶100

We can avoid such displacement by asking the Kantian question—How is educational experience possible, especially for whom?—doing it in the Hegelian style, grasping its possibility as its agent experiences it. Here the non-Hegelian character of Dewey’s program of reconstruction becomes apparent. The changed conditions supported a pedagogical Aufhebung in which the child heaves herself up into a new, more abstract educational situation. Still, having heaved herself up into the school, the child remains the child, and the full set of conceptual resources meaningful outside the institutional context carry over into the new context, significant and important to the child. She continues to construct her possible educational experience with all those powerful concepts, which Dewey deprecated as parts of pernicious dualisms.

¶101

Think of education-as-preparation, which in Democracy and Education Dewey wonderfully debunked as the pedagogical poohbahs then and now propound it. But he let the displacement stand by debunking the misuse without really affirming its proper use. As a pedagogical concept, education-as-preparation has immense importance and value to the person pursuing self-formation. Even for the poohbahs, education-as-preparation might seem to involve some serious meditation on Max’s Weber’s two great essays on the vocations of science and politics, but in our brave new world of public life serious preparation by the poohbahs seems to pass as entirely unneeded. (Weber, 2009) But the child, the real agent of education, engages the question of education-as-preparation continuously, seriously, in work and in make-believe.

¶102

Children, all of us, engage in shaping ourselves through our unfolding sequence of life choices by preparing for all sorts of futures, quite authentically whether imaginatively or actively, even when the prospective future is absurd. The vital context for the concepts involved in the various dualisms, to which Dewey objected, properly involve the persons engaged together in a world in the effort of mutual self-formation, recognizing one another, working to shape themselves intentionally, against the behavioral conditioning of the forces playing upon them. We do not need to censor or reduce this conceptual repertoire from the past; we need to keep the concepts aligned with their authentic agents as the environment of action changes.

¶103

Something else also: the agents of possible experience act not as roles, but as living persons. The person who became the normal school teacher, had not only to perform the requirements of her office, but to engage qua person with the child qua child in a process of Anerkennen, of reciprocal recognition, not as pupil and teacher, but as two autonomous persons, each able to recognize that the other like herself, has recognized her full humanity. If we think about the concepts on the list of dangerous dualisms from the point of view of the child or youth or person who might use them to construct their experience, we see them all having substantial value in the correct context of use. The lives of real persons, of children and youths and everyone else, are complex, many-sided, continuous, social and interpersonal—each and everyone has a real stake in each and every concept on Dewey’s index.

¶104

Dewey reacted to critical philosophy, particularly Kant’s contribution to it, as a body of doctrine that he did not like because to him it seemed to impede the sound application of intelligence to the conduct of life. Others saw critical philosophy as a Begriff, as itself a concept of both inquiry and construction, enabling a living person to start from a this or that, from a given, proceeding carefully to ask how that given was possible. It has been an extremely fruitful stance since the 1890s. Tom Rockmore’s excellent survey of 20th-century philosophy, In Kant’s Wake, and the essays in John Dewey and Continental Philosophy gathered by Paul Fairfield, explore the possibilities. Had Dewey been less hostile to Kant, Rockmore’s short section on Dewey’s interaction with Kant might have had more meat to survey and something like Fairfield’s collection would probably have been published long before 2010.[69]

¶105

What Dewey missed, we’re missing too, and that’s our problem. His instrumentalism epitomized the virtues of the progressive movement. His instrumentalist commitments—organizing the AAUP, work with leading educational associations, the League for Independent Political Action, American Children’s Theatre, the Social Frontier, The Committee for Cultural Freedom, to name a few—were diverse, high-minded initiatives for the betterment of all. But instrumentalism may have slowly decayed. Are we awakening to find it out of control? High-minded instrumentalism might have been fine, “a faith in intelligence, as the one and indispensable belief necessary to moral and social life.” (LW2: 21) But how does an abstract property like intelligence function as a belief in moral and social life? Who does what with it? What in instrumentalism has worked to keep it high-minded? Suddenly we find ourselves awash in lots of low-minded instrumentalism, in tweets and talking points, bubbles and echo chambers, a ship of state that’s become a ship of fools. Do we clearly know what agents and verbs can jump into action under the banner of instrumentalism? Does Trump: The Art of the Deal illustrate instrumentalism at work, or does it exemplify anti-instrumentalism and why? Google “John Dewey and the NEA”—what’s the relation of the top ten hits to instrumentalism in theory and practice?

¶106

Dewey’s positive goals served good purposes. He generally backed constructive policies, goals and programs that would pass Rawlsian tests of justice as fairness, and he advanced them with dedication within his time. But did that result through his philosophy or from his sensibility? Instrumentalism fails to clarify and leaves obscure to what actions by whom it addresses. “Instrumentalism maintains … that action should be intelligent and reflective, and that thought should occupy a central position in life.” (LW2: 19) That’s nice, but it glosses over far too much. Thinking that forgets, obscures, conceals, or disguises the agent who thinks instrumentally about who-knows-what becomes deeply irresponsible by omission or commission.

¶107

We must not rest on Dewey’s laurels. The public still has its problems. We grossly fail to achieve reciprocal recognition of each and all. And both democracy and education, as we know them, have become as much hindrances as helps to humane learning and to a humane public life. Let’s do what Dewey didn’t finish, or even try, let’s work with all the historical resources he might have drawn on. Let’s pay prolonged attention to the intractable problems and to the formative principles in order to educate ourselves, beneath the surface, to build a common life on real foundations.[70]

¶108

Kant stated the three fundamental questions that all share across time and space: What can I know? What should I do? What may I hope? (CPR: A805/B833) Living our lives, constructing our experience, we seek to answer these questions. Let us bear down on them. Among other things….

¶109

What can I know? Let’s undertake a sustained, serious Critique of Education, not another smug complaint about all the wrong that others are doing and not another arrogant pontification about needs and imperatives by a secure commission of distracted souls. How is formative experience possible? What are the limits of its possibility? What do people do that transgress the limits of possible formative experience? What can they do for themselves and others within those limits of possibility? Be prepared—howls of denial will greet a critique of education carried out with fullness, rigor, and clarity of mind.

¶110

What should I do? Let’s work to discover, develop, and practice, within the limits of possible education, how to cultivate the capacities of each for human agency in a world of constraints. If we are not educating ourselves for agency in the midst of real circumstances, we are submitting ourselves to propaganda and manipulation. To get on that path of discovery, development, and practice, we need to stand patiently under the few great efforts, like Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, like Vico, Montesquieu, Rousseau, Herder, Schleiermacher, Marx, Nietzsche, Dilthey, Weber, Dewey too, Ortega y Gasset, Arendt, and all that comes in their train, understanding their most difficult texts, absorbing their spirit while seeking to exceed their grasp.[71]

¶111

What may I hope? Let’s aspire, with humility and hope, to achieve a state of universal recognition in which each feels fulfilled at once in and for herself, a state in which the subjective sense of self that each feels and thinks fully harmonizes with the objective realities each experiences, and a state in which all know with confidence that all are living fully in that state of fulfillment. No one can enjoy such fulfillment in this world as it is, but each and all do expect, need, and merit heaving ourselves up, meaningfully at it, despite the realities of our unhappy consciousness. Without that feeling of meaningful movement, we disengage in resentful alienation from personal and collective life. In this world as it is, we may hope to join in shared effort, inclusive of all, to better approximate the human fulfillment of all.

¶112

Let’s think back to Newberry Hall as Dewey spoke to the students he would soon leave behind. He called to mind the great ideals of a great religion and he must have felt that at Chicago and beyond he would pursue his version of those ideals in his more secular way. Now for us, our quest—rigorously critiquing how education is possible, discovering how to form and educate our human agency in a world of constraint, and working to recognize reciprocally our mutual humanity—more meaningfully expresses the trinity of shared questions in yet different language. Whatever the language, the ideals, the self-expectations, move us with meaning. We all form and pursue them as ordinary humans, and in forming and pursuing his, Dewey made mistakes yet accomplished a lot. His mistakes become cautions for us, his accomplishments become our standard. As humans, no different from Dewey, we have our opportunity to heed his cautions and to improve upon the standards that he and so many others have set through what they were able to know, by what they did, and for which they hoped.

You! The young, take your turn!

Appendix A: The Book and the Précis

¶113

In my view, Dewey based the first 35 paragraphs of “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” primarily on Rosenzranz (1844) and the remaining 120 paragraphs on Hegel (1845). As I explain in note 53, Dewey had two modes of discourse interwoven throughout the text. Direct exposition, the primary one, had Hegel as the subject of the verbs, i. e., “Hegel begins his Philosophy of Spirit with the declaration….” (¶38) In the secondary, Dewey used “we” as the subject, signaling that he would be explaining to his auditors how we, Dewey together with his audience, in a time different from Hegel’s, can best understand what he was saying, i. e., “We are accustomed to think of revelation as an empty form which may reveal this thing or that thing or the other as it happens. … But the spirit reveals precisely itself; the revelation and the revealed are the same thing.” (¶47) Dewey does not speak for himself alone in the text.

¶114

Page 45 shows the correlation for Hegel’s Introductory paragraphs and the Section on Mind Subjective. Page 46 gives the correlation for the 2nd and 3rd Sections, Mind Objective and Absolute Mind. Hegel discussed the material in Mind Subjective much more thoroughly than in Mind Objective and Absolute Mind, averaging 2.25 pages per paragraph in the first and just under .8 in the 2nd and 3rd. Dewey compressed the exposition to about one quarter the length of Hegel’s original and he included coverage of all the different parts of Hegel’s text, consistent with the idea that Dewey’s text gave a careful exposition of what Hegel’s text contained. In contrast, interpretations of one thinker by another characteristically concentrate on those parts of the first thinker’s work most important for the later thinker’s interpretation.

¶115

I think Dewey derived his material in the opening 35 paragraphs largely from the 1st and 2nd books of Rosenkranz (1844). One cannot show a tight correlation, however, because Dewey compressed his exposition radically (to under 7%) relative to Rosenkranz and he mixed in bits of material from Caird (1883). The initial narrative in Dewey’s first 3 paragraphs reflects Rosenkranz with some examples Americanized. Dewey also seems to follow Rosenkranz in drawing significantly from Hegel’s early texts on religion, including two brief quotations that Rosenkranz made. Also, from ¶16 on through ¶26, Dewey characterized Hegel’s initial system as it stood circa 1800, which Rosenkranz did at considerable length (42 pages) at the end of Book 1 of his biography of Hegel. Throughout the initial 35 paragraphs, Dewey used an expository diction, but one that did not use variants on “Hegel said” very much.
37738Introduction (Einleitung)
38141-45What Mind is (Begriff des Geistes)
38246Geist is Freedom
38347Geist is Self-revealing
38448Geist is Absolute
38549Subdivision
38750-52I. Mind Subjective
388-39053-57A. Anthropology. The Soul
39158a. The Physical Soul
392-39559-64(α) Physical qualities
39665(β) Physical alterations
399-40266-68(γ) Sensibility
40369b. The Feeling Soul
40569(α) The Feeling Soul in its immediacy
40770(β) Self-feeling
40972-73(γ) Habit
41173-74c. The Actual Soul
41375B. Phenomenology of Mind. Consciousness
41876a. Consciousness Proper
41876(α) Sensuous consciousness
42077(β) Sense-perception
42278(γ) The Intellect
42479b. Self-Consciousness
42580-81 Hegel criticizes but does not identify Kant, Dewey made it explicit
426-2982-83(α) Appetite
430-3584(β) Self-consciousness recognitive
43685γ) Universal self-consciousness
43885c. Reason
440-4486C. Psychology. Mind
44587a. Theoretical Mind
446-45089-90(α) Intuition
45191(β) Representation
452-45492(1) Recollection
455-46093-98(2) Imagination
46199-101(3) Memory
465102(γ) Thinking
469103b. Mind Practical
471103(α) Practical Sense
473103(β) The Impulses and choice
479103(γ) Happiness
481-482104c. Free Mind
Hegel compressed Sections II & III versus Section I
II & III: (94 paragraphs in 74pp.), I: (106 paragraphs in 241pp)
483105II. Mind Objective
488106A. Law
488106a. Property
493107b. Contract
496-502108c. Right versus Wrong
503109B. The Morality of Conscience (Die Moralität)
*110Dewey interpolated a general explanation using the sophists & Socrates
504111a. Purpose (Der Vorsatz)
505-506112b. Intention (Die Absicht und das Wohl)
507-512113-116c. Goodness and Wickedness
513-517117-118C. The Moral Life or Social Ethics
518119a. The Family
523120b. Civil Society
524121(α) The System of Wants
529122(β) Administrative Justice
533122(γ) Police and Corpoeration
535123-124c. The State
537-546125-126(α) Constitutional Law
547127(β) External Public Law
548-552131-147(γ) Universal History
553148III. Absolute Mind
556149-153A. Art
564153-154B. Revealed Religion
572155C. Philosophy

Endnotes

  1. 1 Andersen, 1837.
  2. 2 See Schilpp, ed. (1939}; White (1943); Dykhuizen (1973); Hickman (1990); Rockefeller (1991); Westbrook (1991); Ryan (1995); Martin (2002); Dalton (2002); & Cochran, ed. (2010)
  3. 3 I cite Dewey from The Collected Works of John Dewey, 1882-1953. Electronic Edition, eds. Jo Ann Boydston and Larry Hickman, (Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2003) by Early Works (EW), Middle Works (MW), Late Works (LW), by volume and page number, e.g. (MW1: 100-5).
  4. 4 To grasp what excited Dewey, see Comte (1880), esp. Introduction, Ch. I, pp. 25-35, and Book VI, Ch. I, pp. 399-439. Comte held that for the past 300 years, Order, grounded in metaphysics, and Progress, driven by empirical science, had conflicted anarchically. A positive social physics needed to replace metaphysics as the foundation of Order, enabling Order and Progress to synthesize constructively.
  5. 5 Dewey’s role at this stage aligned very well to his findings in his “Inventory of Philosophy Taught in American Colleges” (1886), (LW1: 116-121). Strong publications that fit this role included: Psychology(1887) (EW2: 1-365); Leibniz’s New Essays(1888), (EW1: 251-435); “Psychology as Philosophic Method” (1886) (EW1: 144-167); “Knowledge as Idealization” (1887), (EW1: 176-193); “Ethics and Physical Science” (1887), (EW1: 205-226); and “The Ethics of Democracy” (1888), (EW1: 227-249). Within this role, Dewey’s publications devoted much more attention to Kant than to Hegel, perhaps deferring to George Morris as the authority on Hegel.
  6. 6 A typical usage from Porter (1871): 412: “It is not enough, however, that the memory suggests all that she has gathered, unless the imagination reconstructs and recombines in relations as yet untried and unknown.”
  7. 7 I cite Dewey from The Correspondence of John Dewey, ed. Larry Hickman, (Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2008) (CJD), by volume and letter number, e.g. (CJD1: #00125).
  8. 8 See Art as Experience(1934), (LW10: 294). Hickman (1990) illuminates Dewey’s instrumentalism and makes good use of this passage from Dewey.
  9. 9 I cite Dewey from The Class Lectures of John Dewey, ed. Donald F. Koch, (Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2010) (CLJD), with the volume and page number, e.g. (CLJD1: 2247) [Yes, CLJD1 has 2,650 pages; one sees references to CLJD2, but it does not seem available online through InteLex or in print and I have been unable to use it.].
  10. 10 For the beginning, consider how Comte’s negative and positive agenda—break the hold of metaphysics on Western culture in order to introduce social physics as the regulative principle for the conduct of life—had excited the young Dewey. Comte (1880), Book VI, Ch 1, 399-439. For the end, consider this for the negative: “It [scientific naturalism] demands that inquirers turn their backs completely upon formulations of knowledge which are made in terms of any kind of relation or connection which is taken and treated as peculiar to knowledge, whether it be called relation of mind-matter, subject-object, self-world, individual-others, consciousness within— things without, brain— not brain, or whatever.” Dewey (2012): 144.
  11. 11 Kipling (1902)
  12. 12 I should briefly limit this question. Note that in Leibniz(1888) Dewey wrote as in his nascent role as an historian of philosophy and grounded his analysis in texts by Leibniz, Locke, and Kant admirably. Dewey and Tufts grounded both editions of their textbook on Ethicswell in the wide literature relevant to a genetic presentation of ethical thought. From time to time, they employ the concept of reconstruction, both as a process and a program, but within their narrative of historical developments, not with their own program of reconstruction. Dewey cited a full and appropriate grounding for both Art as Experience(1934) and Logic: The Theory of Inquiry(1938), and both point out his program for reconstruction in philosophy, education, and social life, especially with respect to valuable aspects of his positive agenda.
  13. 13 For instance:
    • In Democracy and Education(1916): to provide “a critical estimate of the theories of knowing and moral development which were formulated in earlier social conditions, but which still operate, in societies nominally democratic, to hamper the adequate realization of the democratic ideal.” (MW9: 3)
    • In Reconstruction in Philosophy(1920): “to set forth the forces which make intellectual reconstruction inevitable and to prefigure some of the lines upon which it must proceed.” (MW12: 79)
    • In Human Nature and Conduct(1922): to promote a “morals based upon concern with facts … and guidance from knowledge of them,” … to “put an end to the impossible attempt to live in two unrelated worlds… [and] destroy fixed distinction between the human and the physical, as well as that between the moral and the industrial and political.” (MW14: 11)
    • In Experience and Nature (1925): “The chief obstacle to a more effective criticism of current values lies in the traditional separation of nature and experience, which it is the purpose of this volume to replace by the idea of continuity.” (LW1: 9)
    • In The Quest for Certainty(1929): to overcome the “exaltation of pure intellect and its activity above practical affairs … [and to end] the quest for a certainty which shall be absolute and unshakeable.” (LW4: 5)
    • In Art as Experience(1934): “A primary task is thus imposed upon one who undertakes to write upon the philosophy of the fine arts. This task is to restore continuity between the refined and intensified forms of experience that are works of art and the everyday events, doings, and sufferings that are universally recognized to constitute experience.” (LW10: 9.)
  14. 14 Hall (1887): 156.
  15. 15 EW4: 132-157; MW2: 141-270; MW3: 40-58; MW6: 359-467 & MW7: 209-365; MW13: 399-405; LW8: 3-39; LW13: 191-251
  16. 16 LW1: 69-99, quotation: 98. The chapter quotes, by name without source, Goldenweiser (71-2) as an authority on early culture in one paragraph and Jespersen (pp. 72-3) in another on the origin of language. Dewey also included a quotation from Aristotle on leisure (p. 76).
  17. 17 The “Checklist of Dewey's References,” LW4: 292-3, looks modestly impressive, but long later, the editors of his Works, supplied most of those possible sources, “by reason of place or date of publication, general accessibility during the period, or evidence from correspondence and other materials,” for historical references that Dewey could have made off the top of his head. Almost all the quotations and notes to the text that Dewey made cited prominent recent scientists or science writers, Albert Einstein, James Maxwell, Percy Bridgman, Frederick Barry, Edmund Noble, or Arthur Eddington.
  18. 18 MW8: 184-200 & 421-442; MW10: 221-226
  19. 19 EW3: 237-388; EW4: 219-362; EW5: 54-83, 291-301 MW3: 40-61; MW4: 267-291; MW5: 3-540; MW15: 231-272; LW7: 3-462; LW13: 191-251.
  20. 20 In the conclusion of Leibniz’s New Essays, Dewey pursued an interesting hypothesis that Hume stimulated Kant “to discover the method by which he could justify the results of Leibniz.” That hypothesis led Dewey mainly into Kant’s pre-critical writings, on the basis of which he concluded that “in a broad sense, the work of Kant and of his successors was the discovery of a method which should justify the objective idealism of Leibniz, and which in its history has more than fulfilled this task.” EW1: 428 & 435.
  21. 21 This characterization fits the picture Dewey gave of himself as a youth in “From Absolutism to Experimentalism,” (LW5-147-155, esp. 155) and the impression conveyed by Jane Dewey in her biography of her father in (Schilpp, 1939: 10-30, esp. 21 on the contrast between Dewey and his wife). George Dykhuizen echoes it through the first five chapters of (Dykhuizen, 1973: 1-75).
  22. 22 Dewey’s early article on “Kant and Philosophic Method” (1884) derives heavily, without acknowledgement, from Morris (1882).
  23. 23 In 1890-91, Dewey gave an advanced undergraduate course on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, using (Mahaffy & Bernard, 1889), the use of which Dewey described in a short review (EW3: 184-5). At the same time he gave a course on Caird’s Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, (Caird, 1889) for graduate students. For notes from both courses by Eliza Sunderland, see (Sunderland, 1891).
  24. 24 Dewey’s AWOL dissertation on “The Psychology of Kant” might expand this picture but a few anticipatory lines in a letter early in 1884 to William Torrey Harris provide the fullest description of it. (CLD1: #00429, 01/17/1884)
  25. 25 I have spent much of my career reflecting on intellect, higher education, and public culture and the following paragraphs rest on those reflections. The notes to chapters 2 and 3 in Delbanco (2012) give a fine orientation to current literature on the history and ethos of the American college and university. Publish or perish practices often cast a shadow over older scholarship of lasting quality. For instance, Schneider (1946) gives an excellent survey of philosophy in the United States through the early 20 th century. Rudolph (1962), a good general history of the American college and university, provides informative background to Delbanco’s reflective views. Many of the well-chosen documents centered on the late 19 th and early 20 th centuries in the 2-volume collection of documents on American higher education, Hofstadter & Smith (1961), give participants’ sense of what was taking place. Hofstadter (1961) and Metzger (1961) interpret the intellectual life of the old-time college and emerging universities through issues of academic freedom. Bledstein (1976) and Reuben (1996) interpret the cultural drives and implications of the emergence of the modern university in contrasting ways, and Ringer (1969) depicts a contrast to both for German academic culture in response to some of the same social developments. For authoritative coverage of educational situation, see Cremin (1980) & Cremin (1988). Holborn (1964) provides the cultural situation in the German area in 1650 to 1850 and McClelland (1980) introduces the social history of the German universities in the 18 th & 19 th centuries. Kloppenberg (1986) opens up the comparative intellectual history, Europe and the United States, 1870-1920, a topic that merits more work.
  26. 26 Hawkins (1960: passim.) showed how Daniel Coit Gilman and the Hopkins trustees worked hard to ensure that faculty members had “dependable” religious outlooks.
  27. 27 For Kant’s biography, see Kuehn (2001).
  28. 28 See Nauen (1971), particularly his first chapter on the setting, for a sense of their situation, institutional and intellectual.
  29. 29 Stedman Jones (2016) gives a full and informative discussion of Marx’s educational experience from Gymnasium through his doctoral studies in his recent biography.
  30. 30 For Nietzsche’s education and studies up to his establishment at Basle, see Blue (2016).
  31. 31 What follows in this and the next four paragraphs goes over ground from which an immense literature has grown and about which I will say only a little. Over the years I have found many histories, commentaries, critiques, and interpretations stimulating, some of those most to my liking are a bit out of the mainstream. These have relevance mainly to me personally; I don’t try to say anything on their authority. With someone such as Kant—Hegel, Plato, Ortega, Weber, and increasingly Arendt—I try to understand, which has a special meaning for me of standing underthe work, not quarreling with it, trying to grasp what it is saying and why. I consider myself more an historian, perhaps a somewhat weird one, than a philosopher, because I am not particularly concerned to decide whether Kant reasons correctly as long as I can understand what he is trying to do and why and how. We are all thrown into a world that profoundly mystifies us, swimming in a sea of uncertainty. I do not know, and can learn something, perhaps, by taking another’s best efforts, trying to make sense of them, possibly concluding that this helps construe my situation a bit better and maybe that doesn’t. I say what I say about Kant on my own authority, recognizing that neither I nor Kant, or anyone else, really knowwissenin the strong sense—what we are talking about. I say it in the hope that I may be able to say it, or even understand it, a bit better on encountering the reactions of others. That said, I’ve found as a native speaker of English that I can understand Kant and the Critique of Pure Reasonbetter when I remind myself that in German kennenand Erkenntnisdon’t really mean “to know” and “knowledge,” but rather to be awareand awareness. Ask yourself, “What should I understand Kant’s understanding of his Copernican Revolution to have been?”
  32. 32 Kant lived in a time in which personages of significant, but not absolute power held widely divergent views, a situation to which we are increasingly becoming attuned. What did Kant feel he had to say? He should say? He might be able to say? He would say, no matter what? Schmidt, ed. (1996) helps greatly in trying to understand possible answers to these questions.
  33. 33 Dewey’s appreciation of Kant peaked around 1889-1891 with his enthusiastic review of The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kantby Edward Caird. (EW3:.180-4) Caird sympathetically criticized Kant for not quite succeeding in using noumenato give reason a way to escape encapsulation in a thorough phenomenalism. Caird softened this criticism by observing that Kant provided the phenomenal self an immanent path to “the divine Spirit in man and without him which, through all the process of consciousness and self-consciousness, is realising the highest Good of all his creatures.” Caird admitted that in pointing to this path, he was reading into the letter of Kant’s work the course immediately taken by his successors, culminating in “the Idealistic Optimism of Hegel.” (Caird, 1889, II: 645) As Dewey’s allegiance to Hegel cooled in the next few years, this immanent path in Kant’s work faded away and Dewey was left with a Kant whose metaphysical claims through the noumena had floundered.
  34. 34 Paul Guyer’s chapter on the transcendental deduction of the categories concludes that “Formally speaking, the transcendental deduction is a failure, and at best sets the agenda for the detailed demonstration of the role of the categories in the determination of empirical relations in space and especially time in the following sections of the Critique of Pure Reason. Nevertheless, the transcendental deduction also completely transformed the agenda of modern philosophy.… Kant clearly perceived that there was some inescapable connection between self-knowledge and knowledge of objects, … setting new agendas for subsequent philosophical movements from German idealism to logical positivism and the linguistic philosophy of our own times.” Guyer (1992: 155)
  35. 35 William James, Psychology, I: xiii. (James, 1890: 8:462)
  36. 36 Late February, 1897, Dewey gave an important lecture “On the Significance of the Problem of Knowledge” (Levine, 2016: 1897.2.27, and EW5: 4-24 for the text, published later that year as a pamphlet). In it, Dewey clearly distanced himself from Kant as the last attempt to salvage metaphysics and epistemology: “I venture one more and final unproved statement, believing, with all my heart, that it is justified both by the moving logic of the situation, and by the signs of the times. I refer to the growing transfer of interest from metaphysics and the theory of knowledge to psychology and social ethics—including in the latter term all the related concrete social sciences, so far as they may give guidance to conduct.” (EW5: 22) Psychology and the social sciences would guide conduct to fruition with philosophy providing helpful methods to persons seeking to use the fruits of those sciences in action. This melding of psychology into the social sciences in his program of reconstruction helps to explain Dewey’s later inability to resist how figures like Edward L. Thorndike made psychology the dominant ground for the study of education in schools of edudation like Teachers College, Columbia University. See Lagemann, (2000: Chapter 2)
  37. 37 Searching the text of Democracy and Educationfor “education is” yields 63 hits. Some, of course, are parts of verbs in the passive voice, but a great many are definitional. Adding “education as” gives another 30.
  38. 38 George Santayana, "Dewey's Naturalistic Metaphysics," The Journal of Philosophy22, no. 25 (12/03/1925) 673-688, quotation 680.
  39. 39 For Hegel generally, I use G. W. F. Hegel, The Oxford University Press Translations. Electronic Edition(Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2000) and G. W. F. Hegel, Werke II. Electronic Edition(Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2003). I have found the Hathi Trust invaluable in assessing Dewey’s engagement with the work of Hegel in the early 1890s for access to original sources in German and English, translations, and works on Hegel by William Torrey Harris, G. Stanley Hall, Josiah Royce, etc.
  40. 40 Good in Shook & Good, 2010: 60.
  41. 41 Good & Garrison, 2010a: 61.
  42. 42 Shook (2000).
  43. 43 Good (2006a): passim.
  44. 44 Garrison (2006), Hickman (2008), Alexander (2008) Good (2008), Good & Garrison (2010a & 2010b), Morse (2011), Midtgarden (2011), Grigoriev (2012), Särkelä (2013), Pearce (2014), and Renault (2016).
  45. 45 Johnston (2014): esp. Chapter 2.
  46. 46 In studying the origins of Dewey’s instrumentalism, Morton G. White analyzed this documentary basis with great care. I concur with his conclusion: “This paper of 1891 (“The Present Position of Logical Theory” (EW3: 125-141) still defends Hegel. But it is the last great defense of Hegel to be found in Dewey's logical writings.” (White, 1943: 94) Subsequent exploration of Dewey’s “permanent Hegelian deposit” has aimed significantly at revising interpretations of Dewey’s mature work as a rejection of early Hegelian influence in favor of Darwin, James, and 20-century social science. I think the earlier assessments rest on stronger documentary evidence.
  47. 47 Until Morris died in 1889, for numerous reasons, Dewey’s engagement with Hegel amounted only to what he described in 1930: Morris’s enthusiastic and scholarly devotion” and his reading in the work of British Hegelians, Thomas Hill Green, John and Edward Caird, William Wallace, and the group led by Lord Haldane. (LW5: 152). In a small philosophy department with faculty members spread thin, a junior member does not try to horn in on his patron’s special interest. Dewey did not occupy himself much with Hegel during Morris’s lifetime. He taught the general history of philosophy and the department’s courses in philosophical psychology. Getting started in his professional and personal life, Dewey had to work with a well-formed Hegelian framework for Dewey, one in which he had mastered the key principles of Hegelian thinking without developing a thorough acquaintance with Hegel’s major works.

    Dewey did a lot with that general Hegelian framework. Writing from Ann Arbor late in 1885 to Alice Chipman, he said “I couldn’t resist the temptation to write some on that Hegel idea, which I did, but I fear too fluently.” (CJD1: #00002, 12/31/1885) “That Hegel idea” informed his textbook, Psychology, which readers immediately perceived to have fit the particulars of empirical psychology into a comprehensive Hegelian framework. William James complained to correspondents that he couldn’t finish the book, having started it with high hopes (William James to George Croom Robertson (CJD1: #09540, 12/27/1886), to Thomas Davidson (CJD1: #09529, 01/12/1887), and to G. Stanley Hall (CJD1: #09206, 01/30/1887); on reading Psychology,George Herbert Palmer spotted Hegel as its master “and the more obviously so as [Dewey] never mentions the unpopular name” (CJD1: #16206, 09/23/1887); and G. Stanley Hall expressed his amazement in a review: “That the absolute idealism of Hegel could be so cleverly adapted to be ‘read into’ such a range of facts, new and old, is indeed a surprise as great as when geology and zoology are ingeniously subjected to the rubrics of the six days of creation.” Hall (1887: 156) Although Dewey clearly presented the materials of psychology in an Hegelian framework, he did not mention Hegel in the book, even in discussing the philosophic orientation of his sources (EW2: 364-5).

  48. 48 When Dewey returned to head the philosophy department at the University of Michigan in the fall of 1889, he began to both teach and publish more actively on Kant and Hegel. We will see that Dewey’s Hegelian enthusiasm peaked between 1890 and 1892, shortly after George Morris died, then tapered off, exhausted by the time Dewey went to Columbia. Let’s give due diligence to the early sources. They were thin. Two articles had some substance on Hegel: “On Some Current Conceptions of the Term ‘Self’” (1890 EW3: 56-74) and the last half of “The Present Position of Logical Theory” (1891, EW3: 132-141) A two-and-a-half-page review of a book on Hegel’s philosophy of religion (1890, EW3: 187-190), information in autobiographical texts (LW5: 147-160 & Jane Dewey, 1939), and remembrances of George Morris (EW3: 3-13 & MW10: 109-115) add a little insight. Three letters from the early 90s add more insight: one to Thomas Davidson (CJD1: #00448, 10/26/1890), one to William James (CJD1: #00458, 05/06/1891), and a recommendation for Eliza Jane Read Sunderland about her 1892 Ph.D. dissertation on Kant and Hegel (CJD1: #00490 ,06/23/1894). Finally, paragraphs here and there in three early essays—Kant and Philosophic Method” (1884-EW3:43-7) & “Psychology as Philosophic Method” (1886-EW3: 153-167); and “Psychology as Philosophic Method” (1886-EW5: 344)—and quite a few scattered references elsewhere, all show acquaintance with Hegel’s thought.
  49. 49 Dewey’s writing about Hegel clustered 1890-1892. Sarting in 1892, the frequency and depth of references to Hegel in publications and correspondence dropped off significantly (one must discount correspondence with Edward Carl Hegeler in testing this assertion). In 1891, potential allies—Thomas Davidson and William James—responded to Dewey’s enthusiasm for Hegel with courteous resistance (CJD1: #00453, 03/04/1891, to Thomas Davidson, and CJD1: #00458, 05/06/1891, to William James). In the summer of 1891, Dewey lectured on Hegel’s Aestheticsand his Philosophy of Spiritat Glenmore, a prestigious summer retreat/school organized by Thomas Davidson—lectures in the morning on selected philosophical and literary topics, afternoons and evenings free in the Adirondack countryside. We would say that Glenmore served as a great place for networking, Thomas Davidson’s métier, but Dewey must have noted how J. Clark Murray brought his charming essay on “A Summer School of Philosophy” to a close: “But the intellectual labour that is done evidently imposes no load upon the mind that is not readily shaken off; in fact it may be questioned whether the brief strain of the lectures does not often produce a natural rebound into the lighter moods of thought and feeling. At all events it was currently reported that occasionally ladies, who had been deep in Hegel’s Aesthetics, might be heard a few minutes afterwards seeking a concrete embodiment of their abstract speculations in a discussion over a charming novelty in hats.” (Murray, 1892: 112) The following summer, Dewey returned, lecturing on Comte and on the tendencies of 19 th -century English thought. (Levine, 2016)
  50. 50 In discussing the text, I will refer to it as published in Shook & Good (2010) by the paragraph numbers that they have included. The Hathi Trust has a copy of the 1897 typed version ,digitized from the University of California Library. The title page reads:

    H E G E L ‘ S

    PHILOSOPHY OF SPIRIT

    Lectures

    by

    JOHN DEWEY

    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO

    For Private Circulation Only:

    All Rights Reserved.

    CHICAGO

    1897

    Editorial notes about Dewey’s course material inform readers that it was “a mimeographed typescript for Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit class lecture notes, 103 pp.” for 1897-1898. We also learn that for 1895-96 and 1896-97 Dewey had announced but not given the course. Further, “a similar set of class lecture notes for Dewey’s 1891 Hegel lectures, handwritten by Eliza Jane Read Sunderland … indicates that Dewey had worked out his Hegel lectures by 1891.” (CLJD1, p. 401) Having worked with the manuscripts, Shook and Good also describe them, stating that Sunderland’s 1891 text is “very similar” to the 1897. They go on: “considered together, these two lectures indicate that Dewey was well versed in the details of Hegel’s intellectual development, his German context, and his writings and that Dewey was still quite sympathetic to Hegel as late as 1897.” (Shook & Good, 2010: 93-174, with references, 175-176, and Notes, 190-192). Having looked for it, I am unaware of textual evidence of active engagement with Hegel’s writings taking place after 1892.

  51. 51 Although Dewey occasionally quoted Caird, Dewey relied directly on Rosenkranz as his main source for the first 35¶¶. For instance, unsourced quotations of Hegel in ¶9 & ¶16 came from Rosenkranz, p. 56 & 88. The general structure of the narration follows Rosenkranz, significantly compressing the first 200 pages of Hegels Lebeninto 20. Dewey phrased the material well, sometimes strikingly (e.g. ¶9), but in substance it derives from Rosenkranz, a solid source that Otto Pöggeler, a major Hegel scholar, republished in 1977 (Rosenkranz, 1977: 567-9).
  52. 52 Dewey’s ¶¶41-48 deal with the important early section of Hegel’s book on the concept of spirit, his ¶¶381-384. In discussing what Dewey says here, James Scott Johnston (2014: 62-3) gives an example of how Woozlers convert Dewey’s exposition of Hegel’s text into a full-fledged interpretation of his thought. Johnston begins: “Dewey has Hegel say that nature is the ‘presupposition’ of Spirit, and Spirit the ‘negation of nature’.” He goes on for a page and a half with quotations from Dewey’s text and in the middle of it, 4 italicized sentences, the first being, “ Notice that Spirit as Dewey understands it is not merely the mind, or subject, or thought….” In fact, Dewey did not have Hegel sayanything; he reported that Hegel saidit. The text did not involve spirit as Dewey understood it, it stated how Hegel understood it.

    Dewey’s course on Hegel’s Philosophy of Spiritfollowed spring 1891 his course on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, for which he used Mahaffy & Bernard (1889) as a text. Recall that Dewey thought highly enough of that exposition of Kant’s great work to publish a notice commending its usefulness as an instructional resource: the part on the Critique is “a paraphrase and condensation, with occasional explanatory and critical remarks, which are, however, carefully distinguished from the exposition. The plan of the work is such and its carrying-out so careful and accurate that it fills a position not occupied by any other of the numerous Kant expositions.” (EW3: 185) For his Hegel course, nothing like Mahaffy & Bernard existed and Dewey prepared his own, emulating this model with occasional explanatory and critical remarks carefully distinguished from the exposition. In casting the text as Dewey on Hegel, the Woozlers make Dewey out a hypocrite. In my turn, having roundly criticized Dewey in his mature work for a loosey-goosey relation to his sources in historical exposition, I should give him full credit here for grounding what he had to say about Hegel’s book closely on the text.

  53. 53 See below, “Appendix A: The Book and the Précis,” which correlates the paragraphs in Dewey’s text to the paragraphs in Hegel’s Philosophie des Geistes. The relation between the two text shows that Dewey composed his as a compressed exposition of what Hegel said in the third volume of his Enzyklopädiewith some interpolations such as Dewey’s ¶110 to clarify Hegel for his auditors. Dewey had two modes of discourse interwoven throughout the text. Direct exposition, the primary one, had Hegel as the subject of the verbs, i.e., “Hegel begins his Philosophy of Spirit with the declaration….” (¶38) In the secondary, Dewey used “we” as the subject, signaling that he would be explaining to his auditors how we, Dewey together with his audience, in a time different from Hegel’s, can best understand what he was saying, i.e., “We are accustomed to think of revelation as an empty form which may reveal this thing or that thing or the other as it happens. … But the spirit reveals precisely itself; the revelation and the revealed are the same thing.” (¶47) Dewey does not speak for himself alone in the text.
  54. 54 In their Preface, Shook and Good give their fullest account of their textual criticism of the 1897 manuscript, concluding that “the 1897 lecture complements evidence in his published writings to support the view that, during the 1890s, Dewey shifted from neo-Hegelianism to a humanist/historicist reading of Hegel and that the latter interpretation of Hegel left a far more significant deposit in his mature thought than neo-Hegelianism. On this view, Dewey’s mature philosophy can be seen to be a non-Marxist and nonmetaphysical type of left Hegelianism.” Here Shook and Good engage in wishful thinking. They say the 1897 manuscript is very similar to the notes Eliza Sunderland made of Dewey’s 1891 course and conclude from that similarity that Dewey repeated “his primary views on Hegel during much of the 1890s.” They aver they “cannot pause here to compare in detail” the material, but let us do so for them.

    Two of Sunderland’s notebooks on the Bentley Historical Library microfilm pertain to Dewey’s 1891 course on “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit.” For the first, Sunderland used a steno pad, with lined relatively narrow pages spiral bound at the top. Here she took notes on three course meetings, the first undated giving the sources pertinent to the course, notes in hurried handwriting discernably following how the 1897 text biographically introduced Hegel, concluding with a brief introduction of Hegel’s book on The Philosophy of Spirit(¶¶1-40+/-). The second, dated April 6, ’91, begins with the relation of Spirit to Nature, ¶41, in Hegel’s introductory materials through ¶74 on the Actual Soul, completing the exposition of Anthropology. The third, dated May 4 th 1891, begins with the transition from Anthropology to Phenomenology, ¶75, and ends rather obscurely in the middle of a discussion of Theoretic Mind, circa ¶92. This notebook then ends with some decontextualized notes, seemingly on Kant and Hume. This notebook does not tell us much beyond showing a general similarity between the 1891 class agenda and the 1897 text.

    But the second notebook reveals much more. Sunderland wrote less hurriedly, more legibly, in a lined booklet bound down the center, under the heading “Hegel’s Phil of Spirt last half.” She gave no indication of class meetings. The opening paragraph begins “There are various stages in the process by which the meaning of the obj becomes part of the self….” To one familiar with the 1897 document, it has a familiar ring. Last half, let’s see, ah! ¶92, the opening sentence is exactly that, “obj” spelled out to “object.” From there, her notebook contains ¶¶92-99, copied word for word with minor abbreviations and slight differences like “i. e.,” instead of “that is to say.” Then ¶¶100 and 101 have a few sentences omitted but ¶¶102-106 are copied word for word. ¶107, line 4, ends mid-line and mid-sentence, and then after some space left blank the text picks up mid-sentence, ¶113, line 10, word for word. Sunderland continued to copy ¶¶114-122 word for word until another gap, ¶123, line 13, to ¶127 line 13, breaking off and starting up mid-sentence. And finally she copied ¶¶124-155, word for word to the end. The way the gaps broke off and started up suggests that Sunderland was working from a copy of Dewey’s text missing two or three pages. I think the transcription shows that Dewey wrote “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” late 1890 to early 1891 as material for his spring course on that topic, which he paired with the fall course on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason.

  55. 55 Like Shook and Good, and many others, I would like to think of Dewey’s thought as “a non-Marxist and nonmetaphysical type of left Hegelianism,” but in the context of 1891, we must see “Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit” reinforcing his original neo-Hegelianism. After 1891-92, Dewey had little to say about Hegel until a quarter century later he started roundly criticizing Hegel as a metaphysician legitimating the German authoritarian state, for whom “the ideal authority of truth, goodness, and beauty are secure possessions of ultimate Being independently of experience and human action.” ( Quest for Certainty, 1929, LW4: 52)
  56. 56 In 1890, William Torrey Harris published a major study, Hegel’s Logic: A Book on the Genesis of the Categories of the Mind, in a prestigious series that George Morris edited. For a short time, Dewey became the interim editor of it when Morris died in 1889. Harris devoted over a fifth of his study to Hegel’s Phänomenologie, which he explored as Hegel’s “Voyage of Discovery.” Dewey corresponded with Harris about publication of the book, but to my knowledge Dewey showed no substantive interest in it.
  57. 57 Good (2010: 62) claims that “In the second section [¶¶35-37], Dewey discusses the Phenomenologyfor three paragraphs.” Actually, in ¶35, Dewey referred to the preface to the Phenomenologyfor some of Hegel’s colorful put-downs of his erstwhile friend, Schelling. The paragraph really concerned Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel and the next two, possibly still referring to portions of the preface and possibly anticipating The Philosophy of Spirit, Dewey gave a good encapsulation of major themes in Hegel’s thought. In Dewey’s published writings, he referred to Hegel’s Phenomenologyonly once (1902), in a 3-paragraph entry in vol. 2 of the Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology. (MW2: 188-9) It required no engagement with the text.
  58. 58 However, ¶¶80-1 in the précis interpolate a comparison between Hegel’s transition from consciousness to self-consciousness to Kant’s deduction of the categories. Hegel’s Zusatzto ¶425 discussed the problem of “abstract self-consciousness,” to which Dewey attached the historical name. Dewey would make many such clarifications for his auditors through the text as they would not bring to the discussion the degree of familiarity that Hegel presumed.
  59. 59 This and the following five paragraphs give the gist of my views formed through reading over several decades most of Hegel’s work as well as diverse contributions to the secondary literature. The published version of “Dewey in His Skivvies” took some flak for not cloaking my views with the authority of secondary sources. I will continue to advance my views on my own authority.
  60. 60 It boggles the mind that somehow the widely used translation for Begriffbecame notion. Begriffand begreifen, the noun and the verb, indicate the powerful activity of conceptualizing engaged in the world. No verb goes with “notion” except “to note,” at a distance. Completing the 8 volumes on Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe(Koselleck, et al. eds., 1972, 2004) has recently exemplified German scholarship at its best. Can one imagine calling a similar effort in English, Basic Historical Notions?
  61. 61 Critics have found my ideas about the interpretation of aufhebenparticularly in need of covering citations. When I first started studying German long ago, I found a book from my father’s school days explaining the phonetic and conceptual relations between English and German, commending study of them as a good learning aid. Alas, the book has since gone astray and I cannot cite it, but with what it taught I figured the equivalence of upheaveand aufhebenmyself. German and English have many words that we might call deep cognates. The links between them become apparent if one babbles the words, paying close attention to how one controls the passage of air with different configurations of tongue and lips. For aufthe lips narrow, but don’t close; for upthe lips gently close momentarily and then open narrowly as if for sounding an “f” thus transforming aufto up. Such shifts take place easily over distance and time. Likewise, band vhave minimal phonetic differences and vowels easily wander a bit. The verb upheaveeven harkens back to its German roots as the prefix, “up”, separates in German style—I heavedit up. And for readers who really don’t trust such do-it-yourself explorations, try the etymological entry for upheavein the OED online.
  62. 62 Hobbes, Leviathan, Pt. I, Ch. 14, has natural law, “by which men are commanded to endeavour peace,” driving the process, with the originating contract following from the expression of that law. Locke in the Second Treatise, described roughly the same process with slightly different clauses to the resultant contract. For them, natural law was a given; for Hegel Geistwas a self-creation, with lots of contingency to the steps along the way.
  63. 63 It would take us too far afield here, but the implications of Hegel’s basing cultural and political life on the reciprocal recognition of self and other as self-aware and self-forming agents, rather than parties to a contract that converts a putative natural law into a compact securing civil peace or the protection of property, has powerful implications for the sort of polity people aspire to inhabit. Anerkennendeepens the sense of mutual commitment among people and leavens the locus for social democracy.
  64. 64 Thirty-eight years later, a passage from The Quest for Certainty, partially quoted already, uncannily reprises this one. “Hegel's system may be looked on as a triumph in material content of the modern secular and positivistic spirit. It is a glorification of the here and now, an indication of the solid meanings and values contained in actual institutions and arts. It is an invitation to the human subject to devote himself to the mastery of what is already contained in the here and now of life and the world, instead of hunting for some remote ideal and repining because it cannot be found in existence. In form, however, the old tradition remains intact.” Dewey continued, “these meanings and values, their ‘absolute’ character, is proved by their being shown to be manifestations of the absolute spirit according to a necessary and demonstrative logical development.” And then concluding, “no matter what the detailed conclusions of the special sciences, the ideal authority of truth, goodness, and beauty are secure possessions of ultimate Being independently of experience and human action.” (LW4: 51-2)
  65. 65 Santayana (1910): I:284.
  66. 66 If we shoo philosophy into a little world of its own, a priorisynthetic concepts seem very problematic, self-contradictions balancing the tautologies of the a priorianalytic. But if we take philosophy out of its box where the only problems are “problems of philosophy” as they say, and situate it in our lives as we live them, the situation changes. Experiencebecomes what happens for us, with our participation in its formation, at that ever-moving transition between future and past. The a priorisynthetic becomes that conceptual domain of anticipatory thinking by which we try to make experience better rather than worse. We deploy our conceptual resources prior to experience in thinking thoughts that haven’t happened yet. In educating ourselves, we engage conceptually in forming all those synthetic a prioriconcepts with which we seek to conduct our lives as well as we can.

    Situating all abstraction in the worldly lives of the human animal as we live them allows us to form an understanding of historical reasonand a view of education tightly related to that, historical pedagogy. These terms delimit a broad set of concerns that over the past 250 years or so have been mobilizing a recessive counterpoint to more dominant institutional initiatives in public life: the creation of apparent entities—nations, bureaus, corporations, parties, ethnicities, unions, schools, universities, museums, foundations, clubs, and on—with us all using the logic of fictitious persons to endow them with fictitious lives. This dominant strategy has enabled people to greatly improve the conditions of their lives and it may even prove sustainably beneficial provided we do not mistake the fictitious lives of these embodied abstractions for lives more “real” than those we live. Catastrophes build wherever the proportion of persons choosing to live apparatchik lives becomes the prevailing norm.

  67. 67 John Dewey, Democracy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Education(New York: The Macmillan Company, 1916), p. 442. Unlinking the concepts yields a list of topics worth one’s considering in the course of self-formation: academic [intellectual studies], activity, capital [economic], character, conduct, conservatism, culture, discipline, efficiency, emotions, empiricism, ends, environment, experience, general, habit, heredity, humanism, individual, inner, institutionalism, intellect, intelligence, interest, knowledge, labor, logical, means, naturalism, objective, outer, particular, philosophy, physical, practical studies, practice, progressiveness, psychical, psychological, rationalism, soul, subjective, theory, and thinking.
  68. 68 Note the term “participated.” No one, not even the most “influential” thinkers, cause large-scale historical changes. Whether the institutionalization of “education” or the demise of metaphysical thinking, all significant historical change comes about through very complicated, recursive interactions among innumerable persons in all manner of situations. Leadership takes place as many persons decide to emulate one exemplar—a person, group, or idea—rather than another. Dewey’s inability to use history well exemplified a broader, deeper amnesia weakening 20 th -century progressivism in both education and public life. Dewey did not cause it, but he stood as an exemplar of it. No one can simply will its reversal, but we can and should try to exemplify alternatives as well as we can—better than we are doing—so that we can see what happens in subsequent historical movement.
  69. 69 See Rockmore (2006): esp. 88-94 and Fairfield (2010): passim. I think many of the contributions suffer from the urge to inflate Dewey by association with other thinkers of high repute, an urge to which I hope this essay serves as an antidote. For instance, perhaps the most fruitful comparison between Dewey and an continental thinker would have been Wilhelm Dilthey, who received only a meager passing reference. Kloppenberg (1986) provides an excellent general view and a sense of Dewey’s place within it prior to World War I.
  70. 70 I have addressed these and related matters at greater length in a semi-autobiographical essay, Enough: A Pedagogic Speculation(New York: The Reflective Commons, 2012) and in a forthcoming book, Formative Justice(New York: The Reflective Commons, 2018).
  71. 71 In naming figures like these I am trying to indicate what I take to be the intellectual space from which formation of historical reason and historical pedagogy has been beginning to take place. In doing so, I am not saying anything definitive about the intellectual inputs into these concerns, for the list merely indicates something about my intellectual horizon in thinking about them. Others would have a different list and no one would encompass the scope of the whole effort. I think that each person develops, like it or not, a protean field of reference that functions for each as my canon, and the more each does so with sustained self-awareness the better. Suffice that each takes responsibility one’s own canon; the canon, like so many other specious legitimizers, lies beyond the bounds of possible experience.

Bibliography

Acknowledgements: I am grateful to Steve Cohen, Ellen Lagemann, Jinx Roosevelt, Maxine McClintock, and Avi Mintz for helpful comments on drafts and Anne Reinish, a doctoral candidate at the University of Michigan, for help in securing valuable documents. They do not bear responsibility for the views here voiced. Special thanks to Chris Higgins, a master of the editor’s art of not letting an author finish prematurely, and to Joyce Atkinson and the staff of Educational Theory

EW[1-5]:
John Dewey, The Early Works of John Dewey, 1882-1898. (Jo Ann Boydston & Larry A. Hickman, eds., 5 vols. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1972. Electronic Edition.)
MW[1-15]:
John Dewey, The Middle Works of John Dewey, 1899-1924 (Jo Ann Boydston & Larry A. Hickman, eds., 15 vols. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1978. Electronic Edition.)
LW[1-17]:
John Dewey, The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925-1953 (Jo Ann Boydston & Larry A. Hickman, eds., 17 vols. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1985. Electronic Edition.)
CW1:
John Dewey, The Collected Works of John Dewey, 1882-1953. Supplementary Volume 1: 1884-1951 (Jo Ann Boydston &Larry A. Hickman, eds., Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 2008. Electronic Edition.)
CJD[I-IV]:
John Dewey, The Correspondence of John Dewey, 1871-1952 (Vols. I-IV). (Larry A. Hickman, ed., Carbondale: Center for Dewey Studies, 2010. Electronic Edition.)
CLJD
John Dewey, The Class Lectures of John Dewey: Volume I: Political Philosophy, Logic, Ethics (Donald F. Koch, ed., Carbondale: Center for Dewey Studies, 2010. Electronic Edition.)
WWJ[1-19]:
William James. The Works of William James (Frederick H. Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers, and Ignas K. Skrupskelis, eds., 19 vols. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press, [1975 - 1988] 2008. Electronic Edition
CWJ[1-12]:
William James, The Correspondence of William James. (Ignas K. Skrupskelis and Elizabeth M. Berkeley, eds., with the assistance of Bernice Grohskopf and Wilma Bradbeer, 12 vols. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, [1992 - 2004] 2008. Electronic Edition).
Alexander (2008)
Thomas Alexander, "Comments on James Good, A Search for Unity in Diversity," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44, no. 4 (2008): 563-568
Andersen (1837)
Hans Christian Andersen. “The Emperor’s New Clothes” (Jean Hersholt, trans., Odesnse, DK: The Hans Christian Andersen Centre, [1837] 2015) (http://www.andersen.sdu.dk/vaerk/hersholt/TheEmperorsNewClothes_e.html).
Anon [G.S. Hall] (1887)
Anonymous [G. Stanley Hall], "Review of Psychology. The Cognitive Powers by James McCosh; Introduction to Psychological Theory by Borden P. Bowne; Psychology by John Dewey," The American Journal of Psychology 1, no. 1 (Nov., 1887): 146-159
Beiser (2002)
Frederick C. Beiser, German Idealism: The Struggle against Subjectivism, 1781-1801 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002)
Bergson (1922)
Henri Bergson, Durée et simultanéité, à propos de la théorie d'Einstein (Paris: F. Alcan, 1922)
Bledstein 1976)
Burton J. Bledstein, The Culture of Professionalism: The Middle Class and the Development of Higher Education in America (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1976)
Blue (2016)
Daniel Blue, The Making of Friedrich Nietzsche: The Quest for Identity, 1844-1869 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2016)
Boisvert (1982)
Raymond D. Boisvert, "Dewey, Subjective Idealism, and Metaphysics," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 18, no. 3 (Summer, 1982): 232-243
Bosanquet (1892)
Bernard Bosanquet, A History of Aesthetic (London: S. Sonnenschein & Co. , 1892)
Bryant (1896)
William M. Bryant, Hegel's educational ideas (Chicago: Werner School Book Company [c1896])
Butler (1882)
Joseph Butler, The Analogy of Religion to the Constitution and Course of Nature (Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott & Co. 1882)
Caird (1877)
Edward Caird, A Critical Account of the Philosophy of Kant, with an Historical Introduction (London and New York: Macmillan and Co., 1877)
Caird (1883)
Edward Caird, Hegel (Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons, 1883)
Caird (1889)
Edward Caird, The Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant (2 vols., Glasgow: James Maclehose & Sons, 1889)
Campbell (2016)
James Campbell, "Democracy and Education: Reconstruction of and through Education," Educational Theory 66, nos. 1-2 (2016): 39-53
Cochran, ed. (2010)
Molly Cochran, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Dewey (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010)
Coleridge (1872)
Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Aids to Reflection (New York: N. Tibbals & Son, 1872)
Comte (1880)
Auguste Comte, The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte (Harriet Martineau, trans., Chicago: Belford, Clarke, & Co., [1858] 1880)
Cremin (1980)
Lawrence A. Cremin, American Education: The National Experience (New York: Harper & Row, 1980)
Cremin (1988)
Lawrence A. Cremin, American Education: The Metropolitan Experience, (New York: Harper & Row, 1988)
Dalton, 2002
Thomas C. Dalton, Becoming John Dewey: Dilemmas of a Philosopher and Naturalist (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2002)
Delbanco (2012)
Andrew Delbanco, College: What It Was, Is, and Should Be (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2012)
Dewey & Tufts (1908)
John Dewey and James H. Tufts, Ethics (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1908)
Dewey (1897)
John Dewey, "Hegel's Philosophy of Spirit," in Shook & Good, 2010: 93-174
Dewey (1910)
John Dewey, The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy, and Other Essays in Contemporary Thought (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1910)
Dewey (1916)
John Dewey, Democracy and Education: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Education (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1916).
Dewey (2012)
John Dewey, Unmodern Philosophy and Modern Philosophy (Phillip Deen, ed., Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press,2012)
Dewey, Jane (1939)
Jane M. Dewey, ed., "Biography of John Dewey," in Schilpp, ed., 1939, pp. 3-45
Dykhuizen (1973)
George Dykhuizen, The Life of John Dewey (Carbondale: Southern Illinois Press, 1973)
Erdmann (1891)
Johann Eduard Erdmann, History of Philosophy, vol. 2. Modern Philosophy (Williston S. Hough, trans., 3rd. ed., New York: Macmillan & Co., 1892)
Fairfield, ed. (2010)
Paul Fairfield, ed. John Dewey and Continental Philosophy (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 2010)
Fallace (2010)
Thomas D. Fallace, "John Dewey on History Education and the Historical Method," Education & Culture 26, no. 2 (2010):20-35
Feuer (1958)
Lewis S. Feuer, "H. A. P. Torrey and John Dewey: Teacher and Pupil" American Quarterly 10, no. 1 (Spring, 1958): 34-54.
Fischer (1901)
Kuno Fischer, Hegels Leben, Werke und Lehre (Heidelberg: Karl Winter's Universitätbuchhandlung, 1901)
Garrison (2001)
Jim Garrison, "An Introduction to Dewey’s Theory of Functional 'Trans-Action': An Alternative Paradigm for Activity Theory," Mind, Culture, and Activity 8, no. 4: 275-296
Garrison (2006)
Jim Garrison, "The 'Permanent Deposit' of Hegelian Thought in Dewey's Theory of Inquiry," Educational Theory 56, no. 1 (2006): 1-37
Good & Garrison (2010a)
James A. Good and Jim Garrison, "Traces of Hegelian Bildung in Dewey's Philosophy," in Fairfield, 2010, pp. 44-68
Good & Garrison (2010b)
James A. Good and Jim Garrison, "Dewey, Hegel, and Causation," The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, New Series 24, no 2 (2010): 101-120
Good (2006a)
James A. Good, A Search for Unity in Diversity: The "Permanent Hegelian Deposit" in the Philosophy of John Dewey (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2006)
Good (2006b)
James A. Good, "John Dewey's "Permanent Hegelian Deposit" and the Exigencies of War," Journal of the History of Philosophy 44, no 2 (April 2006): 293-313
Good (2008)
James A. Good, "Dewey's 'Permanent Hegelian Deposit': A Reply to Hickman and Alexander," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44, no. 4 (2008): 577-602
Grigoriev (2012)
Serge Grigoriev, "Dewey: A Pragmatist View of History," Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (2012) 173–194
Guizot (1887)
François Guizot, The History of Civilization (2 vols., William Hazlitt, trans., New York: C. Appleton and Company, 1887)
Guyer (1992)
Paul Guyer, "The Transcendental Deduction of the Categories," in Paul Guyer, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Kant (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992): 123-160
Hall (1887)
G. Stanley Hall, "Reviews of Psychology. The Cognitive Powers by James McCosh; Introduction to Psychological Theory by Borden P. Bowne; Psychology by John Dewey", The American Journal of Psychology, Vol. 1, No. 1 (Nov., 1887), pp. 146-159
Harris (1881)
William T. Harris, Hegel's Doctrine of Reflection (New York: D. Appleton and Company, 1881)
Harris (1890)
William T. Harris, Hegel's Logic: A Book on the Genesis of the Categories of the Mind: A Critical Exposition (Chicago: S. C. Griggs and Company, 1890)
Hawkins (1960)
Hugh Hawkins, Pioneer: A History of the Johns Hopkins University (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1960)
Hegel (1450)
G. W. F. Hegel, Frühe Schriften in Hegel (2003)
Hegel (1801)
G. W. F. Hegel, Jenaer Schriften (1801-1807) in Hegel (2003)
Hegel (1807)
G. W. F. Hegel, Phänomenologie des Geistes in Hegel (2003)
Hegel (1817)
G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften. Dritter Teil. Die Philosophie des Geistes in Hegel (2003)
Hegel (1845)
G. W. F. Hegel, Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften. Dritter Teil. Die Philosophie des Geistes, Ludwig Boumann, ed., in Werke, Vollständige Ausgabe, Bd 7, Ab 2. (Berlin: Verlag von Dunder und Humblot, 1845)
Hegel (1874)
G. W. F. Hegel, The Logic of Hegel Translated from the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences with Prolegomena (William Wallace, trans., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1874)
Hegel (1881)
G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of History (J. Sibree, trans., London: George Bell and Sons, 1881)
Hegel (1894)
G. W. F. Hegel, Hegel's Philosophy of Mind Translated from the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences (William Wallace, trans., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894)
Hegel (1895)
G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion (3 vols., E. B. Speirs, trans., London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner, & Co., 1895)
Hegel (1971)
G. W. F. Hegel, Philosophy of Mind, Part III of the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences (Translated by William Wallace, together with the Zusätze in Boumann’s 1845 edition, translated by A. V. Miller and with foreword by J. N. Findlay. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971) in Hegel (2000)
Hegel (1977)
G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit (Translated by A.V. Miller with analysis of the text and foreword by J. N. Findlay. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) in Hegel (2000)
Hegel (2000)
G. W. F. Hegel, The Oxford University Press Translations. Electronic Edition (Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2000)
Hegel (2003)
G. W. F. Hegel, Werke II. Electronic Edition (Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: Philipp Marheineke et al. Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1832-1845. Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2003)
Hickman (1990)
Larry A. Hickman, John Dewey's Pragmatic Technology (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990)
Hickman (2008)
Larry A. Hickman, "Dewey’s Hegel: A Search for Unity in Diversity, or Diversity as the Growth of Unity?", Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44, no. 4 (2008): 569-576
Hobbes (1996)
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Revised Student Edition, Richard Tuck, ed., New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996)
Hofstadter & Smith (1961)
Richard Hofstadter & Wilson Smith, American Higher Education: A Documentary History, 2 vols. (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1961)
Hofstadter (1961)
Richard Hofstadter, Academic Freedom in the Age of the College (New York: Columbia University Press, 1955, 1961)
Holborn (1964)
Hajo Holborn, A History of Modern German: 1648-1840 (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1964)
James (1890)
William James, The Principles of Psychology (2 vols., Cambridge: Harvard University Press, [1890] 1981, in The Works of William James. Electronic Edition, Vol. 8 & 9, Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corp., 2008)
James (2008)
William James, The Correspondence of William James. Electronic Edition. (Volume 6: 1885 - 1889, Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 2008)
Johnston (2006)
James Scott Johnston, "Dewey's Critique of Kant," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 42, no. 4 (Fall 2006): 518-551
Johnston (2014)
James Scott Johnston, John Dewey's Earlier Logical Theory (Albany: SUNY Press, 2014)
Kant (1781)
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (Paul Guyer & Allen W. Wood, trans., New York: Cambridge University Press, [1781], 1998)
Kant (1788)
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason (Mary Gregor, trans., New York: Cambridge University Press, [1788], 1997)
Kant (1790)
Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment (Paul Guyer & Eric Matthews, trans., New York: Cambridge University Press, [1790], 2000)
Kant (1999)
Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (1787) in Gesammelte Schriften (Akademie-Ausgabe), I-XXIII. Electronic Edition. (Charlottesville, VA: InteLex Corporation, 1999)
Kant (1798)
Immanuel Kant, The Conflict of the Faculties/Der Streit der Fakultäten (Mary J. Gregor, trans., New York: Abaris Books, 1979)
Kaufmann (1961)
Walter Kaufmann, Critique of Religion and Philosophy (Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1961)
Kaufmann (1977)
Walter Kaufmann, Future of the Humanities (New York: Reader's Digest Press, 1977)
Kipling (1902)
Rudyard Kipling, Just So Stories for Little Children (New York: Doubleday, Page & Co., 1902)
Kloppenberg (1986)
James T. Kloppenberg, Uncertain Victory: Social Democracy and Progressivism in European and American Thought, 1870-1920 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986)
Koselleck (1972, 2004)
Reinhardt Koselleck, et al., eds., Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe: Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland (Studienausgabe, 8 vols., Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1972, 2004)
Kroner (1977)
Richard Kroner, Von Kant bis Hegel, 2 vols. 3. Auflage (Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr {Paul Siebeck}, 1977)
Kuehn (2001)
Manfred Kuehn, Kant: A Biography (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001)
Lagemann (2000)
Ellen Condliffe Lagemann, An Elusive Science: The Troubling History of Education Research (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2000)
Levine (2016)
Barbara Levine, Chronology of John Dewey's Life and Work (Carbondale: Center for Dewey Studies, 2016)
Locke (1988)
John Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Student edition, Peter Laslett, ed., New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988)
Luqueer (1896)
Frederic Ludlow Luqueer, Hegel as Educator (New York: Macmillan & Co., 1896)
Mahaffy & Bernard (1889)
John P. Mahaffy & John H. Bernard, Kant's Critical Philosophy for English Readers, Vol. 1. The Kritik of Pure Reason Explained and Defended (New York: Macmillan and Co., 1889)
Martin (2002)
Jay Martin, The Education of John Dewey: A Biography (New York: Columbia University Press, 2002)
McCaul (1962)
Robert L. McCaul, "Dewey in College, 1875-1879," The School Review 74, no. 4 (Winter, 1962): 437-456
McClelland (1980)
Charles E. McClelland, State, Society, and University in Germany, 1700-1914 (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980)
McClintock (2012)
Robbie McClintock, Enough: A Pedagogical Speculation (New York: The Reflective Commons, 2012)
McClintock (2018)
Robbie McClintock, Formative Justice (New York: The Reflective Commons, 2018)
Metzger (1961)
Walter P. Metzger, Academic Freedom in the Age of the University (New York: Columbia University Press, 1955, 1961)
Midtgarden (2011)
Torjus Midtgarden, "The Hegelian Legacy in Dewey's Social and Political Philosophy, 1915-1920," Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 47, no. 4 (Fall 2011): 361-388
Milne (1926)
A. A. Milne, Winnie-the-Pooh (London: Egmont, [1926] 2010)
Mintz (2016a)
Avi I. Mintz, “Educational Philosophers’ Neglect of the History of Educational Philosophy,” in Natasha Levinson, ed., Philosophy of Education 2016 (no place: Philosophy of Education Society, 2017)
Mintz (2016b)
Avi I. Mintz, “Dewey’s Ancestry, Dewey’s Legacy, and The Aims of Education in Democracy and Education,” European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy VIII, no. 1, 2016: 23-35
Morris (1874)
George Sylvester Morris, Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (no place or publisher, 1874)
Morris (1880)
George Sylvester Morris, British Thought and Thinkers (Chicago: S. C. Griggs and Co., 1880)
Morris (1882)
George Sylvester Morris, Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: A Critical Exposition (Chicago: S. C. Griggs and Co., 1)
Morris (1887)
George Sylvester Morris, Hegel's Philosophy of the State and of History: An Exposition (Chicago: Scott, Foresman, 1902 [1887])
Morse (2011)
Donald J. Morse, Faith in Life: John Dewey's Early Philosophy (New York: Fordham University Press, 2011)
Murray (1892)
J. Clark Murray, “A Summer School of Philosophy,” The Scottish Review, 19, January 1892: 98-113.
Nauen (1971)
Franz Gabriel Nauen, Revolution, Idealism and Human Freedom: Schelling, Hölderlin and Hegel and the crisis of Early German Idealism (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1971)
Pearce (2014)
Trevor Pearce, "The Dialectical Biologist, circa 1890: John Dewey and the Oxford Hegelians," Journal of the History of Philosophy 52, no. 4 (October 2014): 747-777
Porter (1871)
Noah Porter, The Elements of Intellectual Science: A Manuel for Schools and Colleges (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, [1871] 1891)
Renault (2016)
Emmanuel Renault, "Dewey's Relations to Hegel," Contemporary Pragmatism," no. 13 (2016): 219-241
Reuben (1996)
Julie E. Reuben, The Making of the Modern University: Intellectual Transformation and the Marginalization of Morality (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996)
Ringer (1969)
Fritz K. Ringer, The Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic Community, 1890-1933 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1969)
Rockefeller (2014)
Steven Rockefeller, John Dewey: Religious Faith and Democratic Humanism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1991)
Rockmore (2006)
Tom Rockmore, In Kant's Wake: Philosophy in the Twentieth Century (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006)
Rockmore (2010)
Tom Rockmore, "Dewey, Hegel, and Knowledge after Kant," in Fairfield, 2010, pp. 26-43
Rosenkranz (1844)
Karl Rosenkranz, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's Leben (Berlin: Verlag von Dunker und Humblot, 1844)
Rosenkranz (1858)
Karl Rosenkranz, Apologie Hegels gegen Dr. R. Haym (Berlin: Verlag von Dunker und Humblot, 1858)
Rosenkranz (1874)
Karl Rosenkranz, Hegel as the National Philosopher of Germany (St. Louis: Gray, Baker & Co., 1874)
Rosenkranz (1977)
Karl Rosenkranz, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel's Leben (Otto Pöggeler, Nachbemerkung, Darmstadt: Wissen-schaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1977)
Royce (2004)
Josiah Royce, The Works of Josiah Royce (Electronic Edition, compiled and edited by Mark C. Rooks. Charlottesville: InteLex Corporation, 2004).
Rudolph (1962)
Frederick Rudolph, The American College and University: A History (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1962)
Ryan (1995)
Alan Ryan, John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1995)
Santayana (1910)
George Santayana, The Life of Reason, or the Phases of Human Progress (5 vols., London: Archibald Constable & Co. 1910-1912)
Santayana (1925)
George Santayana, "Dewey's Naturalistic Metaphysics," The Journal of Philosophy 22, no. 25 (12/03/1925) 673-688
Särkelä (2013)
Arvi Särkelä, "Ein Drama in drei Akten: Der Kampf um öffentliche Anerkennung nach Dewey und Hegel," Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 61, nos. 5/6 (2013): 681-696
Schilpp, ed. (1939)
Paul Arthur Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy of John Dewey (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University, 1939)
Schmidt, ed. (1996)
James Schmidt, ed., What Is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1996)
Schneider (1946)
Herbert W. Schneider, A History of American Philosophy (New York: Columbia University Press, 1946)
Seth & Haldane (1883)
Andrew Seth & R. B. Haldane, Essays in Philosophic Criticism (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1883)
Seth (1887)
Andrew Seth, Hegelianism and Personality (Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons, 1887)
Shook & Good (2010)
John R. Shook and James A. Good, John Dewey's Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel (New York: Fordham University Press, 2010)
Shook (2000)
John R. Shook, Dewey's Empirical Theory of Knowledge and Reality (Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 2000)
Stedman Jones (2016)
Gareth Stedman Jones, Karl Marx: Greatness and Illusion (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2016)
Stirling (1865)
James Hutchinson Stirling, The Secret of Hegel: Being the Hegelian System in Origin, Principle, Form, and Matter (2 vols., London: Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts & Green, 1865)
Sunderland (1891)
Eliza Jane Read Sunderland Papers, "Notes from John Dewey's course on Hegel's Philosophy of Spirit." Bentley Historical Library, University of Michigan, Microfilm MF622C
Tocqueville (1856)
Alexis de Tocqueville, The Ancien Régime and the French Revolution (Jon Elster, trans., Arthur Goldhammer, ed., New York: Cambridge University Press, [1856] 2011)
Ueberweg (1888)
Friedrich Ueberweg, History of Philosophy from Thales to the Present Time (2 vols., George S. Morris, trans., New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1888)
Wallace (1894)
William Wallace, Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel's Philosophy and Especially of His Logic (2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894)
Weber (2009)
Max Weber, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (H. H. Gerth & C. Wright Mills, eds., New York: Routledge, 1946, 2009)
Westbrook (1991)
Robert B. Westbrook, John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991)
White (1943)
Morton G. White, The Origin of Dewey’s Instrumentalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1943)